I have bioethics questions that needed to be answered. I will supply with all the material. - Management
I have bioethics questions that needed to be answered. I will supply with all the material.
there are 16 questions that needed to be answered. each question need 1-2 paragraph.
Each question is goo 1 paragraph. we are talking about probably 8-9 pages
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS
PETER SINGER
Abstract: Many people believe that all human life is of equal value. Most of them
also believe that all human beings have a moral status superior to that of
nonhuman animals. But how are these beliefs to be defended? The mere difference
of species cannot in itself determine moral status. The most obvious candidate for
regarding human beings as having a higher moral status than animals is the
superior cognitive capacity of humans. People with profound mental retardation
pose a problem for this set of beliefs, because their cognitive capacities are not
superior to those of many animals. I argue that we should drop the belief in the
equal value of human life, replacing it with a graduated view that applies to
animals as well as to humans.
Keywords: speciesism, animals, disability, ethics, moral status.
Introduction
This essay derives from a talk presented at the conference ‘‘Cognitive
Disability: A Challenge to Moral Philosophy.’’
1
As that title suggests,
cognitive disability does present a challenge to moral philosophy. I focus
here on the challenge it presents to views about moral status that are
widespread both among moral philosophers and in the wider community.
However, the reverse is also true: moral philosophy can and ought to
challenge how we think about people with cognitive disabilities and about
the value of human life. I want to enlarge the sphere of discussion, so that
we are looking not just at people with cognitive disabilities but also at the
way in which our thoughts about moral status relate to beings who do not
have the cognitive abilities that normal humans have. Although there is
among some who write on cognitive disability a strong aversion to
1
The conference was held at Stony Brook University in New York City in September
2008. I dedicate these thoughts to Harriet McBryde Johnson because my presentation at the
conference was the first time since she died that I spoke on issues of intellectual disability. In
recent years, while she lived, whenever I spoke or wrote about intellectual disability, I could
expect an e-mail from her telling me where I was wrong. Knowing that my work would
receive her sharp scrutiny was a spur to defending my views as well as I could. Sadly I’m not
going to hear from her this time.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and
350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
METAPHILOSOPHY
Vol. 40, Nos. 3–4, July 2009
0026-1068
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
comparing humans with nonhuman animals, these comparisons are
unavoidable if we are to clarify the basis of moral status.
Hence I begin with some examples of cognitive abilities that show
significant overlap between some nonhuman animals and some human
beings. I then discuss the widely accepted ethic of ‘‘the equal value
and dignity of all human life,’’ and the various grounds—religious,
speciesist, cognitive-ability-based, and ‘‘slippery slope’’—on which people
have attempted to support this ethic. I argue that this view of universal
and equal human dignity cannot be supported without a drastic revision
to aspects of our morality, which most people do not want to make. As an
alternative, I present a graduated view of the moral status of humans and
nonhuman animals.
Cognitive Abilities in Humans and Animals
Let us consider a few examples of the capacities and cognitive abilities of
nonhuman beings, with regard to IQ and language comprehension. I
specifically want to consider research done on great apes, border collies,
and grey parrots.
Great apes: Francine Patterson of the Gorilla Foundation claims that
the gorilla Koko scored between 70 and 95 on human IQ tests and
understands about a thousand signs. Though this finding is controversial,
there is a substantial amount of uncontroversial research suggesting that
many of the great apes, including gorillas, chimpanzees, bonobos, and
orangutans, can use human sign language and can develop a fair range of
comprehension.
2
At least, it is clear that they understand a number of
signs, and they use a kind of structured syntax. The question of whether
or not we should call this ‘‘language’’ is not my concern here. What is
relevant for this discussion is comparisons with humans with cognitive
disabilities; the point being that if we raise the standard for language to
exclude the signs used by Koko, Kanzi, Washoe, Chantek, or some of the
other signing apes, then we would have to say that some humans at
profound and severe levels of cognitive disability don’t have language
either. We must keep a level playing field for comparisons between
species—in this case between some humans with cognitive disabilities
and great apes.
Dogs: There’s been some interesting recent work on dogs’ abilities to
recognize human spoken language. Border collies, when presented with a
collection of hundreds of different toys with different names, are able to
respond and fetch a particular named object. Tests have demonstrated
that they can comprehend two hundred to three hundred human words.
3
2
See, for example, the essays in part 2 of Paola Cavalieri and Peter Singer, eds., The
Great Ape Project: Equality Beyond Humanity (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1994).
3
See the research by Juliane Kamiski and Sebastian Tempelmann, cited by Virginia
Morell in ‘‘Minds of Their Own,’’ National Geographic, March 2008.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
PETER SINGER568
Grey parrots: Remarkable work was done by Irene Pepperberg with
Alex, an African grey parrot, who died recently. Alex grasped about a
hundred words; of course, parrots are actually grasping spoken human
language and responding to it in the same spoken language—no sign
language here. Alex—and this also goes for other grey parrots that are
being studied—was shown to be not just ‘‘parroting,’’ because he could
answer novel questions. Furthermore, his answers to the questions showed
a grasp of concepts. For example, if Alex was shown a yellow sphere and a
yellow cube and was then asked, ‘‘What’s the same?’’ he would answer,
‘‘Color.’’ When shown a red sphere and a yellow sphere and asked,
‘‘What’s the same?’’ Alex would say, ‘‘Shape.’’ So it seems clear that Alex
understood what was going on with these basic concepts, and he had
modest numerical ability as well, being able to count up to seven.
4
Having considered these examples of nonhuman animal cognitive
ability, let’s look at some human beings with cognitive disabilities. I’m
focusing here on the very bottom of the range: those with profound mental
retardation, and I acknowledge that this is a very small percentage of
people with intellectual disabilities. In fact, the American Association for
Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities says it’s 1 percent. Other
statistics are available that vary slightly on this, but the point is not so
much how many human beings there are in this category but rather the fact
that there are some, for they form the basis on which I will later raise
arguments about claims that all human beings have a certain kind of moral
status. I recognize that for those with a particular concern for people with
cognitive disabilities, this may make what I’m saying less interesting
because I am going to make an argument that concerns the moral status
of human beings in general, as compared to nonhuman animals. There
may also be some who are working with people with disabilities or who are
caregivers or relatives of people with cognitive disabilities who will look at
my examples of severe and profound cognitive disability and say to
themselves that I am not discussing people who are like the people that
they work with or care for. I acknowledge, of course, that people with
cognitive disabilities are not easy to categorize. Obviously the issues are
different depending on the severity of the cognitive disabilities. But let me
reiterate that for the moment I have in mind those with profound mental
retardation as defined below, and the definition is not mine.
According to the American Association on Intellectual and Develop-
mental Disabilities, people with profound mental retardation
� have an IQ range below 25;
� will always require much supervision, though they may acquire
some self-help skills;
4
See Irene Pepperberg, The Alex Studies: Cognitive and Communicative Abilities of Grey
Parrots (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999).
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 569
� have an ability to understand that exceeds their ability to speak;
� may have little or no speech;
� may be capable of following simple directions;
� have no academic skills;
� may be unable to perform any useful work, though with training
may be able to achieve a work-activity level of productivity;
� may appear socially isolated and pay little attention to others except
as it relates to their own needs.
5
Now let us think about nonhuman animals in terms of these capacities.
� IQ: Some nonhuman animals, such as the gorilla Koko, have IQ
ranges significantly above 25.
� Supervision: Animals don’t require much supervision—many of
them get on and always have got on with their lives perfectly well—
often better—without human interference.
� Speech: It is generally true that nonhuman animals have little or no
speech, or what we would call speech, although, as we have seen,
there are exceptions.
� Following simple directions: Many animals, including dogs, can
follow simple directions. Can they acquire skills? Dogs, horses,
dolphins, pigeons, and several other animals can be trained to
perform useful work. In fact, one of the reasons why it is thought
that border collies are good at following human commands is that
traditionally they have been bred to work with sheep and to
respond to commands to separate some sheep from others.
� Social isolation: We are not the only social animals; there is clearly
a wide range of social mammals for whom sociability is very
important. All of the great apes, primates generally, dogs, and
many other nonhuman animals are social beings and develop in
society, respond to the needs of other beings in their group,
communicate with them, reciprocate certain kinds of behavior,
and so on.
Given that there are some humans who are profoundly mentally retarded
and have the characteristics listed above, it is clearly not the case that all
humans have cognitive ability above all nonhuman animals. On the
contrary, we have many nonhuman animals who are significantly above
some human beings in their level of cognitive ability: in particular, they
are above those with profound mental retardation. Our question is: What
ethical significance can we draw from this?
5
Quoted from Taskforce Independence, ‘‘Supported Accommodation for All Who Need
It: A Reality, Not a Dream,’’ available at www.nds.org.au/nsw/Conferences/2007annual/
papers/3.1b_Discussion\%20Paper_Australia.doc. I have been unable to trace the original
source.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
PETER SINGER570
www.nds.org.au/nsw/Conferences/2007annual/papers/3.1b_Discussion\%20Paper_Australia.doc.
www.nds.org.au/nsw/Conferences/2007annual/papers/3.1b_Discussion\%20Paper_Australia.doc.
www.nds.org.au/nsw/Conferences/2007annual/papers/3.1b_Discussion\%20Paper_Australia.doc.
The Equal Value of All Human Life?
Consider this statement by Pope John Paul II: ‘‘As far as the right to life is
concerned, every innocent human being is absolutely equal to all others.
. . . Before the moral norm which prohibits the direct taking of the life of
an innocent human being there are no privileges or exceptions for anyone.
It makes no difference whether one is the master of the world or the
‘poorest of the poor’ on the face of the earth. Before the demands of
morality we are all absolutely equal.’’
6
This represents a widely held
ethical position, not merely the position of a religious leader or of
someone with a Christian or, more specifically, a Roman Catholic
viewpoint. It expresses a kind of ‘‘official morality’’ that is often applied
in statements about people with cognitive disabilities. Most people pay lip
service to it, though I’m not sure how many really hold it when it comes to
the crunch. I will argue that this doctrine cannot be sustained in the light
of the facts that I have been referring to—or at least not without a very
drastic revision to aspects of our morality, which most people don’t want
to make.
Here is the problem: Can we justify attributing equal value to all
human lives, while at the same time attributing to human life a value that
is superior to all animal life? Of course Pope John Paul II’s statement does
not say, ‘‘All human life is absolutely equal but all humans are superior to
animals,’’ but obviously that is implied by the statement, and by the fact
that while popes very frequently denounce abortion and euthanasia, no
pope has yet denounced the unnecessary killing of animals for food,
although such killing takes place on a vastly larger scale than abortion
and euthanasia. (The number of animals killed for food each year is in the
tens of billions, vastly greater than the entire human population of the
planet, and that does not include fish and other marine creatures.)
Clearly, Pope John Paul II and those who accept his position on this
issue think not only that all humans are equal to each other but also that
they are far superior to nonhuman animals. The philosophical problem is
whether we can justify that view.
In what follows, I briefly discuss three general attempts to ground such
a view, dividing them into three categories: religious, speciesist, and those
that depend on cognitive abilities.
Religious Grounds
As Pope John Paul II’s statement indicates, obviously there is a variety of
religious grounds upon which people might attempt to justify the doctrine
of both the equal worth of all human life and human superiority over
6
John Paul II, Evangelium Vitae, 1995.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 571
nonhuman animals. For example, religious grounds might include the
following:
1. We are made in the image of God, and animals are not.
2. God gave us dominion over animals.
3. We have immortal souls, and animals do not.
I do not think there is any good evidence for any of these claims. I regard
them all as false. Some people may believe that these are true claims. I
would argue, however, that even if they are true, such claims should not
be the basis of law or public policy in a society that is not based on a
religious creed or religious profession. The desirability of keeping church
and state separate is sufficient basis for saying that even those who accept
these religious claims should agree that in a pluralist society they should
not suffice for making laws that regulate how we treat human beings and
nonhuman animals.
Speciesist Grounds
I use the term ‘‘speciesism’’ deliberately, to make a parallel with other
‘‘isms’’ that we are familiar with, particularly racism and sexism. There
are a number of arguments that fall into this general category. Sometimes
they are made by quite respectable philosophers—for example, Bernard
Williams, who defends the view that since we humans are doing the
judging, we are entitled to prefer our own kind.
7
In response to an
example in his article about an imaginary situation in which humans are
being conquered by aliens, and the aliens defend their conquest by
claiming, truthfully, that they are intellectually superior to us and have
better, richer, and fuller lives than we do, Williams replies that if any
human accepted such an argument, we could respond by saying simply,
‘‘Whose side are you on?’’ Williams then applies this to the case of
animals, arguing that we are entitled simply to say, ‘‘We’re humans here,
we’re the ones doing the judging; you can’t really expect anything else but
a bias or prejudice in favor of human beings.’’ This seems to me to be a
very dangerous way to argue, precisely because of the parallel to which I
adverted above. I do not see that the argument is really different from a
white racist saying, when it comes to a question about how one should
treat people of different races, ‘‘Well, whose side are you on? We’re the
ones doing the judging here, why don’t we simply prefer our kind because
it is our kind?’’
We cannot claim that biological commonality entitles us to superior
status over those who are not members of our species. In the case of
7
Bernard Williams, ‘‘The Human Prejudice,’’ which appears, along with a response from
me, in Peter Singer Under Fire, edited by Jeffrey Schaler (Chicago: Open Court, forth-
coming).
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
PETER SINGER572
applying this to people with severe and profound cognitive disabilities,
there is also a problem about saying who the ‘‘we’’ are. What is really
important about saying ‘‘us?’’ Is it that we are all capable of under-
standing language, and perhaps even rational argument? In that case, I
am not addressing those who are profoundly mentally retarded. Or is it
that I am addressing all those who are members of my species? I think it is
much more important that the ‘‘we’’ of this statement are beings of at
least a certain level of cognitive ability. So, if it happens that one of you is
an alien who has cleverly disguised yourself in a human shape, but you are
capable of understanding this argument, I am talking to you just as I am
talking to members of my own species. In important respects, I have
much more in common with you than I do with someone who is of my
species but, because he or she is profoundly mentally retarded, has no
capacity for verbal communication with me at all. In other words, if we
take Williams’s question ‘‘Whose side are you on?’’ to refer to being on
the side of those who share our species membership (as he presumably
intended it), it is a bad argument. If on the other hand we take it to refer
to being on the side of those capable of sharing in discussions of right and
wrong, it clearly does not support the claim that all humans are equal.
There is another claim that one often hears: that humans and no others
have intrinsic worth and dignity, and that is why humans have superior
status. This is really just a piece of rhetoric unless it is given some support.
What is it about human beings that gives them moral worth and dignity?
If there is no good answer forthcoming, this talk of intrinsic worth and
dignity is just speciesism in nicer terms. I do not see any argument in the
claim that merely being a member of the species Homo sapiens gives you
moral worth and dignity, whereas being a member of the species Pan
troglodytes (chimpanzees) does not give you worth and dignity. Some-
thing more would need to be said.
Superior Cognitive Abilities
Some have attempted to justify superior moral status for humans on the
basis that humans have superior cognitive abilities. Many people refer to
Immanuel Kant’s moral philosophy as providing justification for the
claims that human beings are ends in themselves, and that humans have
both worth and dignity, while animals do not. In Kant’s view, ‘‘Animals
are not self-conscious and are there merely as a means to an end. That end
is man.’’
8
Kant’s argument for why human beings are ends-in-themselves
is that they are autonomous beings, which, in terms of Kantian philoso-
phy, means that they are capable of reasoning. Note that Kant goes from
defending the value of autonomy or self-consciousness to maintaining
8
Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Ethics, translated by Louis Infield (New York: Harper
Torchbooks, 1963), p. 239.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 573
that ‘‘man’’ is the end. If we really take his argument seriously it means
that human beings who are not self-conscious—because perhaps they are
so profoundly mentally retarded that they lack self-consciousness or self-
awareness— are also merely means to an end, that end being autonomous
or self-conscious beings. So the Kantian approach is not going to help
those whose objective is to demonstrate that all human beings have
superior status to nonhuman animals.
Those who see morality as a social contract are also likely to link moral
status to higher cognitive capacities. According to this view, the core of
morality is that I agree not to harm you, in return for your agreement not
to harm me.
9
Some cognitive abilities are required to be capable of
forming and adhering to an agreement of this kind. If you are profoundly
mentally retarded, you may not have those abilities. You certainly are not
likely to have them to an extent that is superior to that of some
nonhuman animals, who have been shown to be capable of reciprocity.
As with the Kantian argument, therefore, a contractarian account of
morality is unable to justify granting all humans a moral status superior
to that of any nonhuman animal, though it may justify granting some
humans a moral status superior to that of some humans and of any
nonhuman animal.
So to reiterate: because of the overlap in cognitive ability between
some humans and some nonhuman animals, attempts to draw a moral
line on the basis of cognitive ability, as Kant and the contractarians try to
do, will require either that we exclude some humans—for example, those
who are profoundly mentally retarded—or that we include some nonhu-
man animals—those whose levels of cognitive ability are equal or superior
to the lowest level found in human beings. Hence we have to conclude
that the standard ethical view that we find expressed in the statement by
John Paul II—the view that all human beings, irrespective of their
cognitive abilities, have equal moral status, and that this status is superior
to the moral status of the most intelligent nonhuman animals—cannot be
defended. We find ourselves in need of an alternative to the status quo.
An Alternative View
There are a number of possible alternatives to the view that all human life
is of equal value, and this value is superior to that of any nonhuman
animals. We could:
1. preserve equality by raising the status of animals, granting them the
same status we now grant to humans; or
9
The social contract view can be found in ancient Greece, for example in the position of
Glaucon, as represented in Plato’s Republic. Its most famous exponents are Thomas Hobbes,
John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and in our own era, John Rawls and David
Gauthier.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
PETER SINGER574
2. preserve equality by lowering the status of humans to that which we
now grant to animals; or
3. abandon the idea of the equal value of all humans, replacing that
with a more graduated view in which moral status depends on some
aspects of cognitive ability, and that graduated view is applied both
to humans and nonhumans.
I assume that we can all agree in rejecting (2). I am to some extent
sympathetic to (1) but not in every respect. Alternative (3) remains a
possibility; let us consider how we might go in that direction.
Long before most people were contemplating any serious degree of
concern for animals, Jeremy Bentham, the founding father of the English
school of Utilitarianism, wrote, ‘‘The question is not, ‘Can they reason?’
nor, ‘Can they talk?’ but, ‘Can they suffer?’’’
10
That is indeed a crucial
question to ask whenever we are talking about beings who are capable of
suffering and one that is clearly relevant to how we should treat both
humans and nonhuman animals. Can they suffer? Can they enjoy life? If
so, they have interests that we should take into account, and we should
give those interests equal weight with the interests of all other beings with
similar interests. We should not discount their interests in not suffering
because they cannot talk or because they are incapable of reasoning; and
we should not discount their interests in enjoying life, in having things
that are fulfilling and rewarding for them, either. The principle of equal
consideration of interests should apply to both humans and animals.
That’s the sense in which I want to elevate animals to the moral status of
humans.
I imagine that many people who care for profoundly mentally retarded
humans would support Bentham’s idea that the ability to talk or to
reason is irrelevant to the importance of avoiding suffering and facilitat-
ing an enjoyable life. But Bentham’s principle many not apply to all
aspects of human or animal life. Consider a comment from Roger
Scruton, a conservative British philosopher who defends the killing and
eating of animals, although only if they are well treated during their life
and not, for example, reared on modern intensive farms. Killing animals
is not, Scruton says, wrong in itself, because ‘‘there is a real distinction,
for a human being, between timely and untimely death. To be ‘cut short’
before one’s time is a waste—even a tragedy. . . . No such thoughts apply
to domestic cattle. To be killed at thirty months is not intrinsically more
tragic than to be killed at forty, fifty, or sixty.’’
11
One of the reasons Scruton thinks that ‘‘untimely death’’ is a tragedy
for a human being is that if a human being is killed before his or her time
10
Jeremy Bentham, Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1789),
chap. 17.
11
Roger Scruton, ‘‘The Conscientious Carnivore,’’ in Food for Thought, edited by Steve
Sapntzis (Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus, 2004), pp. 81–91; the passage quoted is on p. 88.
r 2009 The Author
Journal compilation r 2009 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd
SPECIESISM AND MORAL STATUS 575
there are likely to be achievements that this human being may have
accomplished which he or she will not accomplish. So, if you like, there is
a failure to carry out plans that had been made, and to achieve what the
person wanted to achieve. Cattle, on Scruton’s view, have no plans for the
future, and no accomplishments that they would have achieved, had they
been able to live long longer. We could debate this factual claim, but I
accept the normative view that there is greater significance in killing a
being who has plans for the future—who wishes to accomplish things—
than there is in killing a being who is incapable of thinking about the
future at all but exists either moment to moment or within a very short-
time horizon (for example, a time horizon limited to thinking about
eating something in the near future). It is, other things being equal, much
less a tragedy to kill that sort of being than to kill someone who wants to
live long enough to do the sorts of things that humans typically want to
achieve over the course of their lives. But, of course, if this reason is
invoked to justify killing well-treated animals for food, then this has
implications for the question of whether one can justify ending the life of
a profoundly cognitively disabled human being. One could, after all,
rewrite Scruton’s statement as follows: ‘‘There is a real distinction, for a
cognitively normal human being, between timely and untimely death. To
be ‘cut short’ before one’s time is a waste—even a tragedy. . . . No such
thoughts apply to a being unable to make plans for the future. For such a
being, to be killed at an early age is not intrinsically more tragic than to
die in old age.’’ Of course, this challenges a widely accepted human ethic.
So if you thought that Scruton provided you with a sound justification for
continuing to enjoy steak for dinner (as long as you get humanely raised,
grass-bred beef), you need to think whether you are prepared to accept
the argument in a nonspeciesist way and apply it to all beings who are
unable to make plans for the future.
That there is some significance, as far as the wrongness of killing is
concerned, in whether the being killed can think about the future, seems
to me defensible. How much significance there is in this is a more …
1
THE CHALLENGE OF CULTURAL RELATIVISM
by JAMES RACHELS
“Morality differs in every society, and is a convenient term for
socially approved habits.” Ruth Benedict, Patterns of Culture
(1934)
2.1 How Different Cultures Have Different Moral Codes
Darius, a king of ancient Persia, was intrigued by the variety of cultures
he encountered in his travels. He had found, for example, that the
Callatians (a tribe of Indians) customarily ate the bodies of their dead
fathers. The Greeks, of course, did not do that—the Greeks practiced
cremation and regarded the funeral pyre as the natural and fitting way to
dispose of the dead. Darius thought that a sophisticated understanding
of the world must include an appreciation of such differences between
cultures. One day, to teach this lesson, he summoned some Greeks who
happened to be present at his court and asked them what they would
take to eat the bodies of their dead fathers. They were shocked, as
Darius knew they would be, and replied that no amount of money could
persuade them to do such a thing. Then Darius called in some
Callatians, and while the Greeks listened asked them what they would
take to burn their dead fathers bodies. The Callatians were horrified and
told Darius not even to mention such a dreadful thing.
This story, recounted by Herodotus in his History illustrates a recurring
theme in the literature of social science: Different cultures have different
moral codes. What is thought right within one group may be utterly
abhorrent to the members of another group, and vice versa. Should we
eat the bodies of the dead or burn them? If you were a Greek, one
answer would seem obviously correct; but if you were a Callatian, the
opposite would seem equally certain.
It is easy to give additional examples of the same kind. Consider the
Eskimos. They are a remote and inaccessible people. Numbering only
about 25,000, they live in small, isolated settlements scattered mostly
along the northern fringes of North America and Greenland. Until the
beginning of the 20th century, the outside world knew little about them.
Then explorers began to bring back strange tales.
Eskimos customs turned out to be very different from our own. The men
often had more than one wife, and they would share their wives with
guests, lending them for the night as a sign of hospitality. Moreover,
within a community, a dominant male might demand and get regular
sexual access to other mens wives. The women, however, were free to
break these arrangements simply by leaving their husbands and taking
up with new partners—free, that is, so long as their former husbands
2
chose not to make trouble. All in all, the Eskimo practice was a volatile
scheme that bore little resemblance to what we call marriage.
But it was not only their marriage and sexual practices that were
different. The Eskimos also seemed to have less regard for human life.
Infanticide, for example, was common. Knud Rasmussen, one of the
most famous early explorers, reported that be met one woman who bad
borne 20 children but had killed 10 of them at birth. Female babies, he
found, were especially liable to be destroyed, and this was permitted
simply at the parents discretion, with no social stigma attached to it. Old
people also, when they became too feeble to contribute to the family,
were left out in the snow .to die. So there seemed to be, in this society,
remarkably little respect for life.
To the general public, these were disturbing revelations. Our own way of
living seems so natural and right that for many of us it is hard to
conceive of others living so differently. And when we do hear of such
things, we tend immediately to categorize those other peoples as
backward or primitive. But to anthropologists and sociologists, there
was nothing particularly surprising about the Eskimos. Since the time of
Herodotus, enlightened observers have been accustomed to the idea
that conceptions of right and wrong differ from culture to culture. If we
assume that our ideas of right and wrong will be shared by all peoples as
all times, we are merely naive.
2.2 Cultural Relativism
To many thinkers, this observation—Different cultures have different
moral codes— has seemed to be the key to understanding morality.
The idea of universal truth in ethics, they say, is a myth. The customs of
different societies are all that exist. These customs cannot be said to be
correct or incorrect, for that implies we have an independent standard
of right and wrong by which they may be judged. But there is no such
independent standard; every standard is culture-bound. The great
pioneering sociologist William Graham Sumner, writing in 1906, put the
point like this:
The right way is the way which the ancestors used and which
has been handed down. The tradition is its own warrant. It is not
held subject to verification by experience. The notion of right is in
the folkways. It is not outside of them, of independent origin, and
brought to test them. In the folkways, whatever is, is right. This is
because they are traditional, and therefore contain in themselves
the authority of the ancestral ghosts. When we come to the
folkways we are at the end of our analysis.
3
This line of thought has probably persuaded more people to be skeptical
about ethics than any other single thing. Cultural Relativism, as it has
been called, challenges our ordinary belief in the objectivity and
universality of moral truth. It says, in effect, that there is not such thing
as universal truth in ethics; there are only the various cultural codes, and
nothing more. Moreover, our own code has no special status; it is merely
one among many.
As we shall see, this basic idea is really a compound of several different
thoughts. It is important to separate the various elements of the theory
because, on analysis, some parts turn out to be correct, while others
seem to be mistaken. As a beginning, we may distinguish the following
claims, all of which have been made by cultural relativists:
1. Different societies have different moral codes.
2. There is no objective standard that can be used to judge
one societal code better than another.
3. The moral code of our own society has no special status; it
is merely one among many.
4. There is no universal truth in ethics; that is, there are no
moral truths that hold for all peoples at all times.
5. The moral code of a society determines what is right within
that society; that is, if the moral code of a society says that
a certain action is right, then that action is right, at least
within that society.
6. It is mere arrogance for us to try to judge the conduct of
other peoples. We should adopt an attitude of tolerance
toward the practices of other cultures.
Although it may seem that these six propositions go naturally together,
they are independent of one another, in the sense that some of them
might be false even if others are true. In what follows, we will try to
identify what is correct in Cultural Relativism, but we will also be
concerned to expose what is mistaken about it.
2.3 The Cultural Differences Argument
Cultural Relativism is a theory about the nature of morality. At first blush
it seems quite plausible. However, like all such theories, it may be
evaluated by subjecting it to rational analysis; and when we analyze
Cultural Relativism we find that it is not so plausible as it first appears to
be.
The first thing we need to notice is that at the heart of Cultural Relativism
there is a certain form of argument. The strategy used by cultural
relativists is to argue from facts about the differences between cultural
4
outlooks to a conclusion about the status of morality. Thus we are invited
to accept this reasoning:
1. The Greeks believed it was wrong to eat the dead,
whereas the Callatians believed it was right to eat the
dead.
2. Therefore, eating the dead is neither objectively fight nor
objectively wrong. It is merely a matter of opinion, which
varies from culture to culture.
Or, alternatively:
1. The Eskimos see nothing wrong with infanticide, whereas
Americans believe infanticide is immoral.
2. Therefore, infanticide is neither objectively right nor
objectively wrong. It is merely a matter of opinion, which
varies from culture to culture.
Clearly, these arguments are variations of one fundamental idea They
are both special cases of a more general argument, which says:
1. Different cultures have different moral codes.
2. Therefore, there is no objective truth in morality. Right
and wrong are only matters of opinion, and opinions vary
from culture to culture.
We may call this the Cultural Differences Argument. To many people, it
is persuasive. But from a logical point of view, is it sound?
It is not sound. The trouble is that the conclusion does not follow from
the premise— that is, even if the premise is true, the conclusion still
might be false. The premise concerns what people believe. In some
societies, people believe one thing; in other societies, people believe
differently. The conclusion, however, concerns what really is the case.
The trouble is that this sort conclusion does not follow logically from this
sort of premise.
Consider again the example of the Greeks and Callatians. The Greeks
believed it was wrong to eat the dead; the Callatians believed it was
right. Does it follow, from the mere fact that they disagreed, that there is
no objective truth in the matter? No, it does not follow; for it could be that
the practice was objectively right (or wrong) and that one or the other of
them was simply mistaken.
To make the point clearer, consider a different matter In some societies,
people believe the earth is flat In other societies, such as our own,
5
people believe the earth is (roughly) spherical. Does it follow, from the
mere fact that people disagree, that there is no objective truth in
geography? Of course not; we would never draw such a conclusion
because we realize that, in their beliefs about the world, the members of
some societies might simply be wrong. There is no reason to think that if
the world is round everyone must know it. Similarly, there is no reason to
think that if there is moral truth everyone must know it. The fundamental
mistake in the Cultural Differences Argument is that it attempts to derive
a substantive conclusion about a subject from the mere fact that people
disagree about it.
This is a simple point of logic, and it is important not to misunderstand it.
We are not saying (not yet, anyway) that the conclusion of the argument
is false. It is still an open question whether the conclusion is true or false.
The logical point is just that the conclusion does not follow from the
premise. This is important, because in order to determine whether the
conclusion is true, we need arguments in its support. Cultural Relativism
proposes this argument, but unfortunately the argument turns out to be
fallacious. So it proves nothing.
2.4 The Consequences of Taking Cultural Relativism Seriously
Even if the Cultural Differences Argument is invalid, Cultural Relativism
might still be true. What would it be like if it were true?
In the passage quoted above, William Graham Sumner summarizes the
essence of Cultural Relativism. He says that there is no measure of right
and wrong other than the standards of ones society: The notion of right
is in the folkways. It is not outside of them, of independent origin, and
brought to test them. In the folkways, whatever is, is right. Suppose we
took this seriously. What would be some of the consequences?
1. We could no longer say that the customs of other societies are morally
inferior to our own. This, of course, is one of the main points stressed by
Cultural Relativism. We would have to stop condemning other societies
merely because they are different: So long as we concentrate on
certain examples, such as the funerary practices of the Greeks and
Callatians, this may seem to be a sophisticated, enlightened attitude.
However, we would also be stopped from criticizing other, less benign
practices. Suppose a society waged war on its neighbors for the purpose
of taking slaves. Or suppose a society was violently anti-Semitic and its
leaders set out to destroy the Jews. Cultural Relativism would preclude
us from saying that either of these practices was wrong. We would not
even be able to say that a society tolerant of Jews is better than the anti-
Semitic society, for that would imply some sort of transcultural standard
of comparison. The failure to condemn these practices does not seem
6
enlightened; on the contrary, slavery and anti-Semitism seem wrong
wherever they occur. Nevertheless, if we took Cultural Relativism
seriously, we would have to regard these social practices as also
immune from criticism.
2. We could decide whether actions are right or wrong just by consulting
the standards of our society. Cultural Relativism suggests a simple test
for determining what is right and what is wrong: All one need do is ask
whether the action is in accordance with the code of ones society.
Suppose in 1975, a resident of South Africa was wondering whether his
countrys policy of apartheid—a rigidly racist system—was morally
correct. All he has to do is ask whether this policy conformed to his
societys moral code. If it did, there would have been nothing to worry
about, at least from a moral point of view.
This implication of Cultural Relativism is disturbing because few of us
think that our societys code is perfect; we can think of ways it might be
improved. Yet Cultural Relativism would not only forbid us from criticizing
the codes of other societies; it would stop us from criticizing our own.
After all, if right and wrong are relative to culture, this must be true for
our own culture just as much as for other cultures.
3. The idea of moral progress is called into doubt. Usually, we think that
at least some social changes are for the better. (Although, of course,
other changes may be for the worse.) Throughout most of Western
history the place of women in society was narrowly circumscribed. They
could not own property; they could not vote or hold political office; and
generally they were under the almost absolute control of their husbands.
Recently much of this has changed, and most people think of it as
progress.
If Cultural Relativism is correct, can we legitimately think of this as
progress? Progress means replacing a way of doing things with a better
way. But by what standard do we judge the new ways as better? If the
old ways were in accordance with the social standards of their time, then
Cultural Relativism would say it is a mistake to judge them by the
standards of a different time. Eighteenth-century society was, in effect, a
different society from the one we have now. To say that we have made
progress implies a judgment that present-day society is better, and that
is just the sort of transcultural judgment that, according to Cultural
Relativism, is impermissible.
Our idea of social reform will also have to be reconsidered. Reformers
such as Martin Luther King, Jr., have sought to change their societies for
the better. Within the constraints imposed by Cultural Relativism, there is
one way this might be done. If a society is not living up to its own ideals,
the reformer may be regarded as acting for the best: The ideals of the
7
society are the standard by which we judge his or her proposals as
worthwhile. But the reformer may not challenge the ideals themselves,
for those ideals are by definition correct. According to Cultural
Relativism, then, the idea of social reform makes sense only in this
limited way.
These three consequences of Cultural Relativism have led many
thinkers to reject it as implausible on its face. It does make sense, they
say, to condemn some practices, such as slavery and anti-Semitism,
wherever they occur. It makes sense to think that our own society has
made some moral progress, while admitting that it is still imperfect and in
need of reform. Because Cultural Relativism says that these judgments
make no sense, the argument goes, it cannot be right.
2.5 Why There Is Less Disagreement Than It Seems
The original impetus for Cultural Relativism comes from the observation
that cultures differ dramatically in their views of right and wrong. But just
how much do they differ? It is true that there are differences. However, it
is easy to overestimate the extent of those differences, Often, when we
examine what seems to be a dramatic difference, we find that the
cultures do not differ nearly as much as it appears.
Consider a culture in which people believe it is wrong to eat cows. This
may even be a poor culture, in which there is not enough food; still, the
cows are not to be touched. Such a society would appear to have values
very different from our own. But does it? We have not yet asked why
these people will not eat cows. Suppose it is because they believe that
after death the souls of humans inhabit the bodies of animals, especially
cows, so that a cow may be someones grandmother. Now do we want
to say that their values are different from ours? No; the difference lies
elsewhere. The difference is in our belief systems, not in our values. We
agree that we shouldnt eat Grandma; we simply disagree about whether
the cow is (or could be) Grandma.
The point is that many factors work together to produce the customs of a
society. The societys values are only one of them. Other matters, such
as the religions and factual beliefs held by its members, and the physical
circumstances in which they must live, are also important. We cannot
conclude, then, merely because customs differ, that there is a
disagreement about values. The difference in customs may be
attributable to some other aspects of social life. Thus there may be less
disagreement about values than there appears to be.
Consider again the Eskimos, who often kill perfectly normal infants,
especially girls. We do not approve of such things; a parent who killed a
baby in our society would be locked up. Thus there appears to be a
great difference in the values of our two cultures. But suppose we ask
8
why the Eskimos do this. The explanation is not that they have less
affection for their children or less respect for human life. An Eskimo
family will always protect its babies if conditions permit. But they live in a
harsh environment, where food is in short supply. A fundamental
postulate of Eskimos thought is: Life is hard, and the margin of safety
small.” A family may want to nourish its babies but be unable to do so.
As in many primitive societies, Eskimo mothers will nurse their infants
over a much longer period of time than mothers in our culture. The child
will take nourishment from its mothers breast for four years, perhaps
even longer. So even in the best of times there are limits to the number
of infants that one mother can sustain. Moreover, the Eskimos are a
nomadic people—unable to farm, they must move about in search of
food. Infants must be carried, and a mother can carry only one baby in
her parka as she travels and goes about her outdoor work. Other family
members help whenever they can.
Infant girls are more readily disposed of because, first, in this society the
males are the primary food providers—they are the hunters, according to
the traditional division of labor—and it is obviously important to maintain
a sufficient number of food providers. But there is an important second
reason as well. Because the hunters suffer a high casualty rate, the adult
men who die prematurely far outnumber the women who die early. Thus
if male and female infants survived in equal numbers, the female adult
population would greatly outnumber the male adult population.
Examining the available statistics, one writer concluded that were it not
for female infanticide…there would be approximately one-and-a-half
times as many females in the average Eskimo local group as there are
food-producing males.
So among the Eskimos, infanticide does not signal a fundamentally
different attitude toward children. Instead, it is a recognition that drastic
measures are sometimes needed to ensure the familys survival. Even
then, however, killing the baby is not the first option considered.
Adoption is common; childless couples are especially happy to take a
more fertile couples surplus. Killing is only the last resort. I emphasize
this in order to show that the raw data of the anthropologists can be
misleading; it can make the differences in values between cultures
appear greater than they are. The Eskimos values are not all that
different from our values. It is only that life forces upon them choices that
we do not have to make.
9
2.6 How All Cultures Have Some Values in Common
It should not be surprising that, despite appearances, the Eskimos are
protective of their children. How could it be otherwise? How could a
group survive that did not value its young? It is easy to see that, in fact,
all cultural groups must protect their infants:
1. Human infants are helpless and cannot survive if they are
not given extensive care for a period of years.
2. Therefore, if a group did not care for its young, the young
would not survive, and the older members of the group
would not be replaced. After a while the group would die
out.
3. Therefore, any cultural group that continues to exist must
care for its young. infants that are not cared for must be the
exception rather than the rule.
Similar reasoning shows that other values must be more or less
universal. Imagine what it would be like for a society to place no value at
all on truth telling. When one person spoke to another, there would be no
presumption at all that he was telling the truth for he could just as easily
be speaking falsely. Within that society, there would be no reason to pay
attention to what anyone says. (I ask you what time it is, and you say
Four oclock: But there is no presumption that you are speaking truly;
you could just as easily have said the first thing that came into your
head. So I have no reason to pay attention to your answer; in fact, there
was no point in my asking you in the first place.) Communication would
then be extremely difficult, if not impossible. And because complex
societies cannot exist without communication among their members,
society would become impossible. It follows that in any complex society
there must be a presumption in favor of truthfulness. There may of
course be exceptions to this rule: There may be situations in which it is
thought to be permissible to lie. Nevertheless, there will be exceptions to
a rule that is in force in the society.
Here is one further example of the same type. Could a society exist in
which there was no prohibition on murder? What would this be like?
Suppose people were free to kill other people at will, and no one thought
there was anything wrong with it. In such a society, no one could feel
secure. Everyone would have to be constantly on guard. People who
wanted to survive would have to avoid other people as much as
possible. This would inevitably result in individuals trying to become as
self-sufficient as possible— after all, associating with others would be
dangerous. Society on any large scale would collapse. Of course, people
might band together in smaller groups with others that they could trust
not to harm them. But notice what this means: They would be forming
10
smaller societies that did acknowledge a rule against murder: The
prohibition of murder, then, is a necessary feature of all societies.
There is a general theoretical point here, namely, that there are some
moral rules that all societies will have in common, because those rules
are necessary for society to exist. The rules against lying and murder are
two examples. And in fact, we do find these rules in force in all viable
cultures. Cultures may differ in what they regard as legitimate exceptions
to the rules, but this disagreement exists against a background of
agreement on the larger issues. Therefore, it is a mistake to
overestimate the amount of difference between cultures. Not every moral
rule can vary from society to society.
2.7 Judging a Cultural Practice to Be Undesirable
In 1996, a 17-year-old girl named Fauziya Kassindja arrived at Newark
International Airport and asked for asylum. She had fled her native
country of Togo, a small west African nation, to escape what people
there call excision.
Excision is a permanently disfiguring procedure that is sometimes called
female circumcision, although it bears little resemblance to the Jewish
ritual. More commonly, at least in Western newspapers, it is referred to
as genital mutilation. According to the World Health Organization, the
practice is widespread in 26 African nations, and two million girls each
year are excised. In some instances, excision is part of an elaborate
tribal ritual, performed in small traditional villages, and girls look forward
to it because it signals their acceptance into the adult world. In other
instances, the practice is carried out by families living in cities on young
women who desperately resist.
Fauziya Kassindja was the youngest of five daughters in a devoutly
Muslim family. Her father, who owned a successful trucking business,
was opposed to excision, and he was able to defy the tradition because
of his wealth. His first four daughters were married without being
mutilated. But when Fauziya was 16, he suddenly died. Fauziya then
came under the authority of his father, who arranged a marriage for her
and prepared to have her excised. Fauziya was terrified, and her mother
and oldest sister helped her to escape. Her mother, left without
resources, eventually had to formally apologize and submit to the
authority of the patriarch she had offended.
Meanwhile, in America, Fauziya was imprisoned for two years while the
authorities decided what to do with her. She was finally granted asylum,
but not before she became the center of a controversy about how
foreigners should regard the cultural practices of other peoples. A series
of articles in the New York Times encouraged the idea that excision is a
barbaric practice that should be condemned. Other observers were
11
reluctant to be so judgmental—live and let live, they said; after all, our
practices probably seem just as strange to them.
Suppose we are inclined to say that excision is bad. Would we merely be
applying the standards of our own culture? If Cultural Relativism is
correct, that is all we can do, for there is no cultural-neutral moral
standard to which we may appeal. Is that true?
Is There a Culture-Neutral Standard of Right and Wrong?
There is, of course, a lot that can be said against the practice of
excision. Excision is painful and it results in the permanent loss of sexual
pleasure. Its short-term effects include hemorrhage, tetanus, and
septicemia. Sometimes the woman dies. Longterm effects include
chronic infection, scars that hinder walking, and continuing pain.
Why, then, has it become a widespread social practice? It is not easy to
say. Excision has no obvious social benefits. Unlike Eskimo infanticide, it
is not necessary for the groups survival. Nor is it a matter of religion.
Excision is practiced by groups with various religions, including Islam
and Christianity, neither of which commend it.
Nevertheless, a number of reasons are given in its defense. Women who
are incapable of sexual pleasure are said to be less likely to be
promiscuous; thus there will be fewer unwanted pregnancies in
unmarried women. Moreover, wives for whom sex is only a duty are less
likely to be unfaithful to their husbands; and because they will not be
thinking about sex, they will be more attentive to the needs of their
husbands and children. Husbands, for their part, are said to enjoy sex
more with wives who have been excised. (The womens own lack of
enjoyment is said to be unimportant.) Men will not want unexcised
women, as they are unclean and immature. And above all, it has been
done since antiquity, and we may not change the ancient ways.
It would be easy, and perhaps a bit arrogant, to ridicule these
arguments. But we may notice an important feature of this whole line of
reasoning: it attempts to justify excision by showing that excision is
beneficial— men, women, and their families are all said to be better off
when women are excised. Thus we might approach this reasoning, and
excision itself, by asking which is true: Is excision, on the whole, helpful
or harmful?
Here, then, is the standard that might most reasonably be used in
thinking about excision: We may ask whether the practice promotes or
hinders the welfare of the people whose lives are affected by it. And, as
a corollary, we may ask if there is an alternative set of social
12
arrangements that would do a better job of promoting their welfare. If so,
we may conclude that the existing practice is deficient.
But this looks like just the sort of independent moral standard that …
Midterm Exam Study Guide
PHI 312: Bioethics | Fall 2018
Due date: Friday, October 12 by midnight
Instructions: Your final exam will take place on Canvas. You will receive five questions
to answer, each chosen from the questions below. Each question will be worth 20 percent
of your final exam. You are welcome to study for the exam with classmates, but all
answers must be your own. Any student who submits an answer that is the same as
another student’s will receive a zero on the exam. Because you will have plenty of time
to study and prepare your answers, I expect them to be clear, concise, and accurate.
Each question can be answered in one to two paragraphs. Although there is no word
limit, you only want to include the information that is absolutely necessary. Superfluous
information gives the impression that you don’t know what is important to the answer
and is as harmful to your grade as missing information. I am grading you not only on
accuracy, but also on whether you understand what information is important and what
information is not. Do not cite or refer to any material we have not covered in class.
Doing so will result in a zero.
Possible Exam Questions
1. The Cultural Differences Argument is an argument about metaethics. What is the
Cultural Differences Argument? Why does the argument fail? Be specific–use an
example.
2. Respect for autonomy is one bioethical principle. What is autonomy? Does everyone
have the same autonomy? What other moral obligations does respect for autonomy
give us?
3. The principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence are also important for medical
ethics. What moral guidance do the principles give us? How are they different?
Finally, how can they conflict with the principle of autonomy?
4. Theories of moral status underly many of our common moral judgements. According
to Singer and McMahan, the common theory of moral status has two problems: the
separation problem and the equality problem. What is the common theory of moral
status? What property/properties does the common theory of moral status take to be
relevant for moral status? People don’t explicitly endorse a theory of moral status, so
how can we tell that most people are committed to a view like this?
5. What is the separation problem? What is the equality problem? Why does the
common theory of moral status lead to these two problems? How does Singer think
we have to respond to these problems?
6. What, according to Singer, is speciesism? How is it like sexism or racism? What
theory of moral status does Singer endorse instead of speciesism, and what are the
main differences between species and Singer’s view?
7. Velleman relies on the Kantian notion of dignity to inform his position on the ethics
of suicide and euthanasia. What is dignity, according to Velleman? How is it
connected to theories of moral status? Which theory of moral status is it most closely
connected to?
8. Which theories of moral status are most conducive to a pro-life position? Which
theories of moral status are most conducive to a pro-choice position? Why?
9. Explain JJ Thomson’s account of the right to life. What is the right to life? How
does this account of the right to life undermine pro-life theories of the ethics of
abortion, according to Thomson?
10. Thomson’s approach to the ethics of abortion implies that sometimes abortion is bad
but not unjust/wrong, and that sometimes abortion is unjust/wrong. When is
abortion bad but not wrong, according to Thomson? When is abortion unjust/
wrong, according to Thomson?
11. Thomson argues that in principle one could believe that abortion is wrong because it
is a rights-violation, but that abortion is permissible in cases of rape. However, this
position is hard to defend. Why does Thomson think that this position is implausible?
12. Marquis thinks that the abortion debate has resulted in a stalemate. Why,
argumentatively speaking, have we arrived at a stalemate in Marquis’s view? How
does Marquis think we can break the stalemate?
13. Explain Don Marquis’s theory of the wrongness of killing. How does this support
the pro-life view of abortion? Why is Marquis’s theory compatible with the
permissibility of contraception?
14. What is dignity, according to Velleman? If we have dignity, why do we not have a
right to end our lives?
15. McMahan gives a conditional argument for the permissibility of active euthanasia.
What is active euthanasia? Briefly reconstruct McMahan’s conditional argument.
16. McMahan argues that rational suicide is permissible. What is rational suicide?
Briefly reconstruct McMahan’s argument for the permissibility of rational suicide.
A Right of Self‐Termination?
Author(s): J. David Velleman
Source: Ethics, Vol. 109, No. 3 (April 1999), pp. 606-628
Published by: The University of Chicago Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/233924
Accessed: 22-08-2016 20:58 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected]
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Ethics
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
A Right of Self-Termination?*
J. David Velleman
Getting cancer changed my feelings about people who smoke.
I remember hearing a fellow philosopher expound, with a wave of
his cigarette, on his right to choose whether to live and die smoking, or
to quit and merely survive. I was just beginning a year of chemotherapy,
and mere survival sounded pretty good to me. But I was the visiting
speaker, and my hosts were unaware of my diagnosis. Several of them lit
up after dinner as we listened to their colleague’s disquisition — they with
amused familiarity, I with an outrage that surprised even me and would
have baffled them, if I had dared to express it. That I didn’t dare is a
cause for regret even now, ten years after the fact.
One objection was already clear to me at the time. A few months with
cancer had taught me that a tumor rarely invades a region smaller than
an extended family.
Physically, the cancer was confined to my body, but even in that re-
spect it was difficult to regard as mine. The tumor cells were growing in
my bone marrow, which didn’t live up to its poetic billing as the core of
my being. The marrow in my bones, I discovered, was as foreign to me as
the far side of the moon: it was, in a sense, my far side —unseen, insen-
sate — its depth inside me being a measure of remoteness rather than
intimacy. Of course, this fertile gunk in my pelvis and skull was also my
sole source of blood cells, and my life depended on it. But so did the life
of my sons’ father, my wife’s husband, my parents’ son, my brothers’
brother, and I was never sure who among us would suffer the greater
harm if that life ran out of gunk.
606
Ethics 109 (April 1999): 606 – 628
! 1999 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. 0014-1704/99/0903-0006$02.00
* Work on this article was supported by a fellowship from the National Endowment
for the Humanities, and by a sabbatical leave from the College of Literature, Science, and
the Arts, University of Michigan. An earlier and very different version was presented to the
philosophy department and the Center for Ethics and Humanities in the Life Sciences at
Michigan State University. I received helpful comments on that version from Elizabeth
Anderson and Stephen Darwall, both of whom have also contributed significantly to my
thinking on this subject through their published work. I also received comments from Bette
Crigger and an anonymous referee for the Hastings Center Report. For comments on the
present version, I am grateful to Sally Haslanger, Connie Rosati, Tamar Schapiro, and Brian
Slattery.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Listening to my host laugh at his future cancer, I wondered whether
he realized how many others would share it. What I would have said on
their behalf, however, wouldn’t have expressed my strongest feelings,
which were felt on my own behalf, in a sense that I couldn’t articulate. I
was somehow offended, insulted. Watching smoke curl from the lips of
people unmindful of my mortality, I felt as I probably would feel listening
to anti-Semitic remarks directed at another person by a speaker unaware
that I, too, was a Jew. I was witnessing an insult to a group of which I was
also a member.
This symposium isn’t about the right to smoke, of course; it’s about the
right to die. Not surprisingly, however, these rights tend to be articulated
in the same terms. A person claiming either right might describe it, for
instance, as a right ‘‘to live and die in the light of . . . his own convictions
about why his life is valuable and where its value lies.’’
I can’t recall whether the speaker in my story used these exact words,
but I seemed to hear his voice again when I read them in the New York
Review of Books, under the title ‘‘The Philosophers’ Brief.’’1 This brief had
been submitted to the U.S. Supreme Court in support of a challenge to
statutes outlawing physician-assisted suicide. Reading it, I once again felt
a collective slight, and this time I couldn’t miss which group was being
slighted.
So I think that I can now explain why I was once offended by one
philosopher’s defense of smoking, and the explanation leads me to re-
ject The Philosophers’ defense of assisted suicide as well. As for assisted
suicide itself, however, I don’t know what to think. The complexities of
the issue have thus far defeated my attempts to arrive at a settled posi-
tion. On the policy question posed by this symposium, then, I am neither
Pro nor Con. I’m, like, Not So Fast.
The principle quoted above, which would settle the issue quickly, can be
derived from two broader principles. The first principle is that a person
has the right to make his own life shorter in order to make it better — to
make it shorter, that is, if doing so is a necessary means or consequence
of making it a better life on the whole for him. The second principle is
that there is a presumption in favor of deferring to a person’s judgment
on the subject of his own good. Together, these principles imply that a
person has the right to live and die, in particular, by his own convictions
about which life would be better for him.
For the smoker in my story, of course, shortening his life was not a
Velleman A Right of Self-Termination? 607
1. Ronald Dworkin et al., ‘‘Assisted Suicide: The Philosophers’ Brief,’’ New York Review
of Books 44 (March 27, 1997): 41– 47. The brief was submitted in the case of Washington
et al. v. Glucksberg et al. Links to briefs and opinions in this case can be found on the World
Wide Web at http://ethics.acusd.edu/euthanasia.html.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
means of making it better but rather a likely consequence of an activity
that made it better, in his opinion, despite making it shorter, too. But
in most of the cases for which assisted suicide is advocated, shortening
a patient’s life is intended as a means of making it better, because the
continuation of the patient’s life would detract from its overall value for
him.2 When the first principle is confined to this latter context, it can
be rephrased as the assertion of a patient’s right to end his life on the
grounds that it is no longer worth living.
I think that this principle is mistaken. Before I criticize it, however,
I should speak briefly to the second principle stated above, which I can
accept. I think that a person’s considered judgment about his good is a
judgment to which we generally ought to defer.
More specifically, then, I think that we generally ought to defer to a
person on the question whether his life is worth living, since the living-
worthiness of a life measures the extent to which the continuation of that
life would be good for the person living it. The person living a life is the
best judge of the value that its continuation would afford him — not an
infallible judge, of course, but usually more reliable than anyone else is
likely to be. Indeed, his judgment of this value is to some extent self-
fulfilling, since his merely liking or disliking aspects of his life can to
some extent make them good or bad for him.
The reasons for deferring to a person’s judgment about his good go
beyond his reliability as a judge. Respect for a person’s autonomy may
require that we defer to his considered judgment about his good even
when we have reason to regard that judgment as mistaken. Letting him
live his own life may sometimes entail letting him make his own mistakes
about what’s good for him — including, perhaps, mistakes about whether
it would be good for him to go on living. Forbidding a person to make
such mistakes can be objectionably paternalistic, because it would usurp
his role as the primary agent of his own affairs.
Thus, if a person had the right to end his life on the grounds that it
wasn’t worth living (in accordance with the first principle, above), then
he would have the right to be guided by his own judgment on that score
(in accordance with the second principle). But I reject the principle that
a person has the right to end his life solely on the grounds of the benefits
he will thereby obtain or the harms he will avoid.
One reason for rejecting this principle is that a life confers benefits and
harms on people other than the person living it. Does a person have the
right to deprive his children of a parent simply because life isn’t worth
enough to him?
I want to set aside this question, however, because it tacitly concedes
608 Ethics April 1999
2. I discuss evaluations of this kind in ‘‘Well-Being and Time,’’ Pacific Philosophical
Quarterly 72 (1991): 48 –77.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
the assumption that the values at stake in life-or-death decisions are rela-
tive to personal interests; it merely invites us to consider a wider circle
of potential beneficiaries. The values that we need to consider, in my
view, aren’t relative to personal interests and consequently have no bene-
ficiaries.
One might insist that values must have beneficiaries, because they
wouldn’t exist if there weren’t someone who could appreciate them:
nothing would be good or bad in a universe devoid of sentient beings.3
But the fact that values wouldn’t exist without potential valuers does not
entail that they must accrue to someone.
Values are relative to potential valuers because they are normative,
in the first instance, for valuation.4 That is, for something to be valuable
just is for it to be such as ought to be valued in some way — respected,
loved, admired, wanted, treasured, or the like. The very concept of value
therefore contains the concept of a valuer, actual or potential.
The experience of valuing something can be beneficial, as in the
case of appreciating the aesthetic value in a work of art. But the concept
of value, in positing a potential valuer, doesn’t necessarily require that
he would benefit from the experience. Things can be venerable, for ex-
ample, whether or not there is any benefit in venerating them; and they
can be awesome whether or not one would gain by holding them in awe.
So the fact that value must be capable of registering with someone, who
would thus appreciate it, does not mean that it must be capable of accru-
ing to someone, who would thus gain by it. Value requires a potential
valuer but not a potential beneficiary.
In fact, our appreciation of values that are relative to the interest of
a beneficiary may depend on a prior appreciation of a value that is not
relational in this sense. This dependence emerges when we try to expli-
cate the concept of interest-relative value, or what is good for a person.
The concept of what is good for a person turns out to be fairly resistant
to explication. We might initially think to equate what’s good for a per-
son with whatever would be rational for him to care about. But this equa-
tion would end up implying that all rational concerns are self-interested,
by definition. In order to allow for the possibility of rational selflessness,
we have to acknowledge that not everything that would be rational for
someone to care about is necessarily in his interest.
Various philosophers have therefore attempted to define what’s
good for a person as a proper subset of the things that would be rational
for him to care about, such as the subset including only those things
Velleman A Right of Self-Termination? 609
3. See Peter Railton, ‘‘Facts and Values,’’ Philosophical Topics 14 (1986): 5 –31.
4. See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1993).
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
which require his existence. It may or may not be a drawback in these
definitions that they would exclude from a person’s good such things as
posthumous fame. In any case, these definitions are still too inclusive,
since the things involving a person’s existence that are rational for him
to care about include, for example, particular sacrifices that he can make
for other people.
The only convincing analysis of a person’s good, to my knowledge,
is one recently proposed by Stephen Darwall, who argues that what’s
good for a person is what’s rational to want for his sake.5 ‘For the sake of ’
is a phrase that marks the subordination of one concern to another: to
care about one thing for the sake of something else is to care about the
former out of concern for the latter. To want something for the sake of a
person is thus to want it out of concern for the person himself. Darwall’s
analysis says that a person’s good is what would be rational to want out of
concern for that person.
Darwall argues — convincingly, to my mind — that a person’s good is
a rational object of desire for anyone who cares about that person. By
the same token, he argues that even the person himself is rationally
obliged to care about his good only insofar as he cares about the person
whose good it is — that is, himself.6
Think here of the familiar connection between how you feel about
yourself and how you feel about your good. Sometimes when you realize
that you have done something mean spirited or shameful, you come to
feel worthless as a person; you may even hate yourself; and one symptom
of self-hatred is a loss of concern for your own welfare. It no longer seems
to matter whether life treats you well or badly, because you yourself seem
to be no good. Your desire for your good thus depends on your concern
for yourself — and rationally so, according to Darwall’s analysis.
Note that self-loathing isn’t the feeling that you are worthless to your-
self. Indeed, the value that things afford to you is precisely what no
longer seems to matter, and so your having no value for yourself wouldn’t
seem to matter, either. The reason why value accruing to you no longer
seems to matter, however, is just that you don’t seem to matter, period.
You have lost your appreciation for the value that things have in rela-
tion to your interest because you have lost a sense of embodying value in
yourself.
Now, things could still be good for you, in Darwall’s analysis, even if you
didn’t embody any value; since they could still be such as would be ratio-
nal for someone to want if he cared about you, however baseless the
610 Ethics April 1999
5. Stephen Darwall, ‘‘Self-Interest and Self-Concern,’’ Social Philosophy and Policy 14
(1997): 158 –78, reprinted in Self-Interest, ed. Ellen Paul (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1997). This article is also the source for my statement of the problem in the preced-
ing section.
6. The points made here and in the following paragraph appear in Anderson, p. 26.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
latter concern might be. But things that were good for you would not
actually merit concern unless you merited concern; and if you didn’t,
then despite their being good for you, they wouldn’t ultimately be worth
wanting, after all. As I put it a moment ago, what’s good for you wouldn’t
matter if you didn’t matter.
This account of a person’s good therefore implies — rightly, again,
in my opinion — that what’s good for a person is not a categorical value,
any more than what’s good for a purpose. What’s good for a purpose is
worth caring about only out of concern for the purpose, and hence only
insofar as the purpose is worth caring about. Similarly, what’s good for a
person is worth caring about only out of concern for the person, and
hence only insofar as he is worth caring about. A person’s good has only
hypothetical or conditional value, which depends on the value of the
person himself.7
Of course, we assume that a person’s good does matter. But we make
this assumption only because we assume that people matter — that every-
one has a value that makes him worth caring about. Darwall’s analysis of
a person’s good reveals how our appreciation of value that accrues to
someone depends on a prior appreciation of a value inhering in him.
The latter value cannot be relative to personal interests, on pain of
setting off a problematic regress. If this value were relative to someone’s
interest, then it would matter only to the same extent as that beneficiary.
This regress of values would continue until it reached a value that was
not relative to anyone’s interest and that consequently mattered for its
own sake. In fact, however, the regress never gets started, because we
assume that every person already matters for his own sake, because of
embodying an interest-independent value.
A value of this kind, which a person has in himself but not for anyone, is
the basis of Kantian moral theory. Kant’s term for this value is ‘dignity’,
and he attributes dignity to all persons in virtue of their rational nature.
What morality requires of us, according to Kant, is that we respect the
dignity of persons.8
The dignity of a person is a value that differs in kind from his inter-
est. Unlike his interest, for example, his dignity is a value on which his
opinion carries no more weight than anyone else’s. Because this value
does not accrue to him, he is in no better position to judge it than others.
Similarly, respect for a person’s autonomy does not require defer-
ence to him on questions of his dignity, as it does on questions of his
Velleman A Right of Self-Termination? 611
7. This point, too, is made by Anderson.
8. Here I am making a leap that requires more justification than I can provide in the
present context. I am equating the value that we appreciate in caring about a person with
the value that we appreciate, somewhat differently, in respecting that person in the Kantian
sense. I defend this equation in ‘‘Love as a Moral Emotion,’’ Ethics 109 (1999): 338 –74.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
good. On the contrary, respect for a person’s autonomy just is an appre-
ciation of a value in him that amounts to a dignity, in Kant’s sense of the
term, precisely because it commands respect. If a person denies embody-
ing such a value, he can hardly claim that we should defer to him out of
an appreciation for a value such as he denies. He cannot claim, in other
words, that out of respect for his autonomy we should defer to his judg-
ment that he possesses nothing worthy of our respect.
Nor is it paternalistic to challenge a person’s judgment about his
dignity, as it is in the case of his good. Challenging a person’s judgment
about his good is objectionable because it undermines his role as the
agent of his own affairs; but his value as a person is not just his affair.
Although his good is a value that accrues to him alone, in the first in-
stance, his value as a person inheres in him among other persons. It’s a
value that he possesses by virtue of being one of us, and the value of
being one of us is not his alone to assess or defend. The value of being
a person is therefore something larger than any particular person who
embodies it.
That’s what I miss in so many discussions of euthanasia and assisted sui-
cide: a sense of something in each of us that is larger than any of us,
something that makes human life more than just an exchange of costs
for benefits, more than just a job or a trip to the mall. I miss the sense of
a value in us that makes a claim on us — a value that we must live up to.
I don’t deny that there are circumstances under which it would be
better for one’s life to end and permissible to hasten its ending. What
I deny is that one may end one’s life simply because one isn’t getting
enough out of it. One has to consider whether one is doing justice to it.
If a person possesses no value that he must live up to, or do justice
to, then his life becomes a mere instrument, to be used or discarded
according to whether it serves his interest. His moral claim to his own
life then looks something like this:
[A] patient’s right to life includes a right not to be killed. But that
right gives [him] a protected option whether to live or die, an op-
tion with which others cannot legitimately interfere; it does not
give [him] a duty to live. If a patient decides to die, he is waiving
his right to live. By waiving his right, he releases others (perhaps a
specific other person) from a duty not to kill him.
This can’t be right. It portrays morality as protecting a person’s options
without protecting the person himself, except insofar as his own exis-
tence is one of his options. Surely, however, options are worth protect-
ing, not for their own sake, but for the sake of the person whose options
they are. So how can morality treat the person as worth protecting only
for the sake of protecting one of his options? If he doesn’t already merit
protection, how can they?
612 Ethics April 1999
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The quotation above is drawn from a recent essay by Frances Kamm, who
goes on to answer Kantian objections as follows: 9
Suppose life involves such unbearable pain that one’s whole life is
focused on that pain. In such circumstances, one could, I believe,
decline the honor of being a person. . . . We might acknowledge
the great (and normally overriding) value of being a person . . .
[and yet] allow that some bad conditions may overshadow its very
great value.
Here Kamm is claiming that someone can view life as a mere option even
while accepting the Kantian view of his value as a person. The problem
with this passage is that it misstates the Kantian view.
When Kamm says that the value of a person normally ‘‘overrides’’
the value of other goods, but can be ‘‘overshadowed’’ by conditions that
are exceptionally bad, she implies that it can be balanced against the
person’s interest. And when she goes on to speak of this value as an
‘‘honor’’ that the person can decline, she implies that it is actually part
of a person’s interest, since an honor accrues to a particular person,
whose role as its beneficiary entitles him to accept or decline it.
But the dignity of a person isn’t something that he can accept or
decline, since it isn’t a value for him; it’s a value in him, which he can only
violate or respect. Nor can it be weighed against what is good or bad for
the person. As I have argued, value for a person stands to value in the
person roughly as the value of means stands to that of the end: in each
case, the former merits concern only on the basis of concern for the
latter. And conditional values cannot be weighed against the uncondi-
tional values on which they depend. The value of means to an end can-
not overshadow or be overshadowed by the value of the end, because it
already is only a shadow of that value, in the sense of being dependent
upon it. Similarly, the value of what’s good for a person is only a shadow
of the value inhering in the person, and cannot overshadow or be over-
shadowed by it.
These are abstract considerations, but they are concretely illustrated by
the story with which I began. When my host claimed that he benefited
more from the pleasures of smoking than he would be harmed by an
early death, my first thought was that he had failed to consider harms
and benefits to people other than himself. On second thought, however,
I resented his assumption that harms and benefits were the only values
at stake.
My host’s remarks implied that an early death, of the sort he was risk-
ing and I was hoping to forestall, would be a loss to him that could be offset
Velleman A Right of Self-Termination? 613
9. Frances Kamm, ‘‘A Right to Choose Death?’’ Boston Review 22 (1997): 20 –23.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
by sufficient gains. But what would it matter how much I lost or gained if I
myself would be no loss? My gains or losses would merit concern only on
the basis of concern for me —which, being the basis of concern for them,
could not then be offset by that concern. Hence my gains or losses
wouldn’t matter unless I had a value that could not be offset by theirs.
My host was implicitly denying the existence of such a value. For he
claimed that death was worth worrying about only in respects for which
he could be compensated by the pleasures of smoking. He was thus
implicitly denying the interest-independent value of a person, without
which it couldn’t really matter whether I lived or died.
Of course, he was denying the existence of this value in his own case,
not in mine; but our cases were indistinguishable on this score. By
implicitly denying his own interest-independent value, my host was
somehow trivializing or denigrating himself as a person. Sometimes
people’s self-denigrating remarks just embarrass us, but in other in-
stances they can be sufficiently principled to give offense. Recall my ear-
lier reference to anti-Semitism. Anti-Semitism can manifest itself in self-
denigrating remarks, if it is the anti-Semitism of a self-hating Jew. My
host’s disregard for his own value as a person offended me as another
person, just as someone’s denigrating himself as a Jew would offend me
as another Jew.
I think Kant was right to say that trading one’s person in exchange for
benefits, or relief from harms, denigrates the value of personhood, re-
spect for which is a criterion of morality (Kant would say, the criterion).
That’s why I think that smoking is a vice — at least, when practiced for
the reasons offered by my host. It’s also why I think that suicide is im-
moral when committed on the grounds that life isn’t worth living.
Mind you, I don’t go around snatching cigarettes out of people’s
mouths. And I’m not sure that I would forcibly try to stop someone from
committing suicide solely because it would be immorally self-destructive.
The impermissibility of someone else’s conduct doesn’t necessarily give
me permission to interfere with it. By the same token, however, I think
that encouraging or assisting others in impermissible conduct is itself
impermissible. That’s why I think that the tobacco industry is engaged
in an immoral enterprise. And it’s why I think the same of Dr. Kevor-
kian, who has done more than anyone to help people die by their own
convictions.
Note that these moral judgments distinguish between self-destruc-
tion and mere self-harm. As I have said, I believe that people are some-
times entitled to act on mistaken judgments about their own interest;
and to this extent, at least, they are entitled to harm themselves. But the
behaviors that I have criticized don’t merely damage the agents’ inter-
ests; indeed, they may not damage the agents’ interests at all, if the
agents are right about the costs and benefits involved. These behaviors
614 Ethics April 1999
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:58:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
are to be criticized, in my view, because they are premised on a disregard
for the value of the agents themselves.
The same criticism would apply, for example, to agents who put up
their own freedom as collateral in order to obtain loans. People have no
right to sell themselves into slavery, no matter what their convictions, but
the reason is not that they would thereby be harming themselves; the
reason is that they would be violating …
Suppose, as I think most people would agree, that it would be permissible to grow
a single organ in this way in order to save a person’s life. If it would be permissible
to grow one organ this way, it should also be permissible to grow two—for example,
if the person needed two organ transplants rather than just one. But, if it would be ac-
ceptable to grow two organs separately, it should be acceptable to grow three, or four,
or five. Imagine that a person has a rare disease that can be cured only by a series of
tissue grafts to most parts of his body. To cure him, it would be necessary to use the
techniques of stem-cell-based biosynthesis to grow organic replicas of most of his
body parts and then graft a small amount of each replica into the corresponding part
of his body. It is hard to see how it could be wrong to grow a set of separate organs
and body parts in this way. It would be macabre, certainly, but it is hard to see how
the organs themselves could have a moral status that would make it wrong to create
them for instrumental purposes, or to use or even to destroy them once they were cre-
ated. But if there is no objection to creating each organ or body part separately, it
ought equally to be acceptable to grow them all together in the form of an anen-
cephalic clone. It would, of course, make a difference if they were grown together as
an organism with a functional brain, for that would involve the existence of a further,
distinct entity with interests and rights. But if the clone is anencephalic, the only dif-
ference is that the organs and parts would be physically integrated and mutually sup-
porting rather than maintained separately, each on its own scaffolding of combined
organic and inorganic support systems. And it is hard to believe that this could make
the difference between permissibility and impermissibility. It seems, rather, that the
intrinsic moral status of an anencephalic clone—that is, the moral status it has based
on its intrinsic rather than relational properties—is no different from that of a collec-
tion of separately grown organs.
2. euthanasia and assisted suicide
2.1. From Suicide to Euthanasia
“Suicide” and “euthanasia” are concepts with blurred edges. It is often unclear
whether a certain act counts as suicide or whether an act is an instance of euthanasia.
These conceptual problems merit discussion, but only a rather brief discussion here.
In the past, some of these questions were thought to have profound significance. For
example, when it was widely accepted that suicides were excluded from heaven, it
seemed of the utmost importance to be able to determine whether a particular act was
an instance of suicide. Here, by contrast, the main point of the conceptual prelimi-
naries is simply to delimit the subject matter of this section of the book.
Let us say that an agent commits suicide if he dies as a consequence of acting
with the intention of bringing about his own death. This allows that suicide can be ei-
ther by act or by omission. It thus treats as an instance of suicide the act of a person
who dies as a result of refusing a life-saving medical treatment on the ground that he
wished to die rather than to continue to live. Yet the definition’s reliance on the no-
tion of intention introduces substantial unclarity. It is clear that a person who acci-
dentally or inadvertently causes his own death does not commit suicide; and it is
equally clear that a person who deliberately kills himself (for example, by putting a
Endings 455
gun to his head and pulling the trigger) does commit suicide. Whether, in the latter
case, the agent intends his own death as an end or whether he intends it as a means to
an end (for example, the punishment of his wife or, perhaps, the relief of his own suf-
fering) is immaterial. I believe, though others have disputed this, that it is also im-
material whether the agent acts under duress or coercion.50 There is nothing para-
doxical about the notion of a coerced suicide. It is also reasonably clear that, when a
person does something that he merely foresees may or will result in his death (such
as playing Russian roulette), he does not necessarily commit suicide. But what about
cases in which a person intentionally uses himself in a way that he believes will re-
sult in his own death? Examples include the soldier in a foxhole who flings himself
on a live grenade to shield his comrades, and the man who deliberately attracts the at-
tention of a deadly wild animal to himself in order to allow his child to escape. Have
such people, when they are killed, committed suicide?
Our inclination is to deny that they have. And certainly it is reasonable to see these
deaths as foreseen but unintended; for, in each case, if the act had accomplished the
person’s aim without resulting in the person’s death (for example, if the grenade had
merely maimed the soldier or if the animal had mauled but not killed the parent), none
of his intentions or plans would thereby have been thwarted. Yet there is another
sense, associated with traditional readings of the Doctrine of Double Effect, in which
these people’s deaths are intentional. To see this, we need only to imagine variants of
the cases in which the agent sacrifices someone else rather than himself. If, for ex-
ample, the soldier were to fling someone else on the grenade, most people would see
this as an instance of intentional killing—that is, an instance of killing one person as
a means of saving others, hence a paradigm of the sort of act that the Doctrine of
Double Effect ought to condemn. Perhaps we should say that, even though the death
would not be an intended effect in the narrow sense distinguished in section 10.1 of
chapter 4, it nevertheless has, because of its relation to the agent’s intentions, the
same significance as an intended effect. If so, the question is then whether, in the orig-
inal cases, the presence of this same relation between the agent’s death and his inten-
tions makes it appropriate to count these cases as instances of self-sacrificial suicide.
I will not pursue these complications here, though I have discussed the analysis
of intention elsewhere.51 Because our concern is primarily with euthanasia, we can
confine our brief discussion of suicide to cases that are relevantly parallel—that is,
cases in which an agent brings about his own death because he believes that his sub-
sequent life would not be worth living, and hence that death would be better for him
than continued life. In these cases, the death is an intended effect on any account.
Next, a few words about the concept of euthanasia. An act of euthanasia, as I will
understand the term, is an act of killing or of letting someone die that satisfies two
conditions: first, that death benefits, or is good for, the individual who dies and, sec-
ond, that the agent must be motivated to do what is good for that individual and must
intend to benefit the individual in bringing about his death. Even if an act that brings
about a person’s death is intended thereby to benefit the person, it does not count as
euthanasia if it is not in fact good for that person. If it would have been better for the
person to continue to live, the act may be an instance of intended euthanasia or at-
tempted euthanasia, but it is not actually euthanasia. Similarly, if an act of killing or
letting die is not intended to benefit the individual who is killed or allowed to die, it
456 the ethics of killing
does not become an act of euthanasia if, fortuitously, it turns out to have been better
for the individual to die rather than to continue to live.
There is an interesting conceptual question that I have never seen discussed in the
literature on human euthanasia. This question arises from a problem frequently en-
countered in veterinary medicine. Suppose that a man brings his dog to the vet and
requests that it be “put to sleep.” When asked why he wants the dog killed, the man
replies that he and his family are going on a long trip and cannot afford to have the
dog kept in a kennel (or that the dog wets the carpet, that the children have lost inter-
est in it, or whatever). Although killing an animal in circumstances such as these is
commonly known as “convenience euthanasia,” it may seem that this is just a euphe-
mism, for it cannot be good for an animal to be killed when it is perfectly healthy. But
there may be more to it than this. The vet may have reason to believe that, if she does
not kill the animal painlessly, its owner will take it away and kill it himself, in a man-
ner that would not be painless, or that he will turn it loose to starve or be hit by a car.
Suppose, in fact, that the man has credibly threatened to do something of this sort.
The vet might, of course, offer to take the animal and give it a home herself. But sup-
pose that she gets two cases of this sort every week—far more animals than she her-
self could care for or even find homes for. In each individual case, then, the situation
is that there is an animal whose life could in principle be worth living but no one is
willing, nor perhaps obliged, to do what is necessary to make it worth living. The vet
therefore has the choice, in practice, between painlessly killing the animal and al-
lowing it to live a life that she has good reason to believe will in fact be worth not liv-
ing. A parallel case could arise in the case of a human being—for example, if a per-
son’s life will be worth not living unless he has a surgical procedure that he cannot
afford and that would be so expensive that no one else is willing or obliged to provide
it for him. In these circumstances, would it count as euthanasia to kill him and could
it be permissible to do so?
Again I raise these questions only to put them aside. I will restrict my attention
here to cases in which it is not possible to change an individual’s life in a way that
would make it worth living.
I will briefly note a few common distinctions and then turn to substantive matters.
Euthanasia is said to be voluntary when a person freely and autonomously requests or
consents to be killed or allowed to die for his own good. It is nonvoluntary when it is
not possible for the individual who is killed or allowed to die either to give or to with-
hold consent. This category, therefore, encompasses all cases of euthanasia in which
the individual killed or allowed to die is a fetus, an infant, an animal, a congenitally
severely cognitively impaired human being, or a human being who has ceased to be
competent to form autonomous preferences about life and death, and who has not
previously expressed his will on the matter. Euthanasia is said to be involuntary when
an individual who is competent to give or withhold consent is killed or allowed to die
either contrary to his expressed will or when his consent has not been sought. (There
may be cases in a gray area between nonvoluntary and involuntary euthanasia in
which an individual, though capable of expressing a preference, lacks the compe-
tence to have an informed, autonomous preference.) Finally, killing an individual for
his own good is commonly referred to as active euthanasia, whereas letting an indi-
vidual die when that is in his best interests is referred to as passive euthanasia.
Endings 457
It has sometimes been remarked that it is difficult to accept that suicide can be
morally permissible without accepting that euthanasia can be as well.52 And indeed
there are only a few short steps between the premise that suicide can be permissible
and the claim that euthanasia can be.
Consider a case in which a person’s life is worth not living: it is and will remain
dominated by pain and suffering that cannot be alleviated and that are not counter-
balanced by compensating goods. Some people, of course, claim that life is always
worth living, or at least that it always can be made to be worth living. But if it is true
that pain and suffering are in themselves bad, it seems that a life that contains little or
nothing but pain and suffering—one, moreover, that is neither redeemed by its good
effects on others nor elevated, ennobled, or enlightened by the experience of suffer-
ing—cannot be worth enduring. I will assume that, when a life is bad in this way for
the one whose life it is, and when that individual’s death would not be worse for any-
one else, it can be prudentially rational for that individual to commit suicide. Most
people accept that, in these circumstances, suicide would also not be immoral. Cer-
tainly few people now accept that someone who commits suicide in such circum-
stances is guilty of murder.
Let us assume, conditionally, that, when suicide is rational and not worse for
others, it is also morally permissible. Most people also accept that there are circum-
stances in which it is permissible to assist someone to commit suicide. Consider, for
example, a case in which a person’s suicide would be rational and not worse for
others but in which the person cannot easily bring about his own death because he is
tethered to a battery of life-support machines from which it would be difficult to ex-
tricate himself. Most of us believe that, in these circumstances, it would be permis-
sible for the person’s physician to accede to his request to collaborate with him in
withdrawing the life-support systems—for example, by assisting the person to re-
move the various pieces of apparatus from his body. Indeed, most of us believe that,
provided that the person is competent, the physician ought to enable him to free him-
self from the machines. Given that the withdrawal of the life-support systems will
lead immediately to the person’s death, we should regard the person’s removal of
them as an act of suicide, albeit an instance of “passive suicide,” since he does not
create the cause of his death but instead allows himself to die by removing the pro-
tections that have thus far been saving him from a preexisting threat. In assisting him
to remove these protections, the physician assists him to commit suicide.
I have described a case in which a person chooses to die “passively” by ceasing
to resist a threat of death that is not of his own making. In most cases, people com-
mit suicide actively, by creating the threat that results in their death. Many people re-
gard it as impermissible to assist someone in actively committing suicide, and it is at
present illegal in most areas of the United State for physicians to assist their patients
in actively killing themselves—for example, by prescribing a lethal dose of some
medicine. Yet it is hard to see how it could be permissible to provide assistance to a
passive suicide but not to an active suicide. How could the permissibility of assis-
tance by a third party depend on whether the person bent on suicide chooses an ac-
tive or a passive means, particularly when either would be equally permissible?
It is tempting to appeal here to the general claim that, if it is permissible for a per-
son to do something, it must also be permissible for others to assist him. But that
458 the ethics of killing
claim seems false. There are, for example, rare circumstances in which one wholly
innocent person will be killed by another wholly innocent person unless the one kills
the other first. In these circumstances, it may be permissible for each to try to kill the
other but not permissible for a third party to assist either. For while it may be per-
missible for each agent to give priority to himself, a neutral third party may be re-
quired to treat both principals equally and impartially and may therefore be forbid-
den to provide assistance to either at the expense of the other.53 But it seems that this
restriction on the permissibility of assistance by third parties applies only in cases in
which what an agent is permitted to do may prevent others from doing what they are
permitted to do or otherwise have adverse effects on others. In the case of a rational
suicide that would not be worse for others, these complications do not arise; there-
fore there is no reason to suppose that a third party may not assist the agent in doing
what it is permissible for that agent to do.
There are, moreover, positive reasons why, in the case of a rational suicide, as-
sistance from others is desirable. People who set out to kill themselves sometimes
fail, leaving themselves not only alive but disabled, disfigured, humiliated, and in
pain. As Arthur Koestler, “speaking in the name of many . . . who tried and failed,”
once observed, “there is only one prospect worse than being chained to an intolerable
existence: the nightmare of a botched attempt to end it.”54 And even when people suc-
ceed in committing suicide, they are often forced to quit life alone, in terror, without
the support or validation of others, and with greater pain and mess than is necessary.
If it is prudentially rational and morally permissible for a person to seek death, how
much better it would be if he could be assured assistance from others that would en-
able him to die with as much comfort, reassurance, and certainty as possible.
Thus far we have passed by short steps from the permissibility of rational suicide
to the permissibility of assisted passive suicide and assisted active suicide. But we
have also, perhaps without noticing it, taken another step as well: to passive euthana-
sia. In the case I cited of assisted passive suicide, the physician assists the patient to
disconnect himself from the life-support systems. But by refusing to collaborate, or
by actively preventing the patient from disconnecting himself, the physician could
have kept the patient alive. Therefore this is a case in which the physician allows the
patient to die. If the physician is motivated to do this at least in part by the true belief
that death would be in the best interest of the patient, her action constitutes an in-
stance of passive euthanasia. It seems, in fact, that this is a case in which the cate-
gories of assisted suicide and euthanasia overlap: the patient commits suicide, with
the physician’s assistance, by refusing to continue to be saved, or kept alive; yet the
physician also allows the patient to die, and does so with the intention of thereby ben-
efiting him.
It would, perhaps, be a more obvious case of passive euthanasia if the physician
alone turned off or disconnected all the life-support systems. Assuming that the sys-
tems she withdrew were all ones that she had herself been providing, this would be
an instance of allowing the patient to die and not a case of killing—in short, a case
of passive euthanasia, despite the fact that allowing the patient to die required action
rather than inaction. Still, in either case—whether the physician assists in the with-
drawal of the life-support systems or removes them entirely by herself—most of us
acknowledge the permissibility of her action. We accept, in short, the permissibility
Endings 459
of at least some instances of voluntary passive euthanasia. For it is widely accepted
that a physician not only may but must comply with a patient’s competent request for
the termination of life-supporting medical aid. And it would seem absurd to suppose
that, while the physician could permissibly remove the patient from life-support
systems, she could not permissibly do so with the intention of benefiting the patient
by enabling him to die.
Passive euthanasia is, however, as far as we as a society have so far been willing
to go. Many people, at least when they consider the matter in the abstract, think that
there is a sharp moral line—one that must not be crossed—between allowing some-
one to die when it is in his interest to die and actually killing him. But when one con-
siders the matter closely, it seems that the step from passive to active euthanasia is
again a very short one. Consider, for example, the activities of the notorious Dr. Jack
Kevorkian. (Let us put aside whatever reservations we may have about his character
and methods: his publicity seeking, megalomania, insufficient knowledge of his
“clients,” and so on.) His earlier cases were instances of assisted suicide: he hooked
people up to a device containing a lethal chemical, but the people themselves actu-
ally pressed the button that released the chemical into their bloodstream. By contrast,
in a more recent case, the person—a man named Youk—suffered from amyotrophic
lateral sclerosis and was so disabled that it was difficult for him to push the button.
He therefore asked Kevorkian to push it for him, which Kevorkian did, with a video
camera rolling all the while. Most of us, on reflection, find it difficult to believe that
it could make a momentous moral difference whether Youk pushed the button him-
self or whether Kevorkian pushed it for him. Yet that is all that the difference between
assisted suicide and killing amounts to.
In addition to the fact that it seems insignificant who pushes the button, provided
that the person whose death it causes autonomously wants it to be pushed, there is an-
other feature this case that supports the inference from the permissibility of passive
euthanasia to the permissibility of active euthanasia. This is Youk’s apparent inabil-
ity to press the button himself. Most people who desperately want to die are capable
of killing themselves and thus seek the assistance of others only in order to ensure
that their own action is painless, minimally shocking to others, and successful. If
we accept the permissibility of rational suicide (subject, of course, to certain con-
straints), and in particular if we accept the permissibility of assisting in the commis-
sion of rational suicide, we are acknowledging that people have a right to die when
life has become an intolerable burden and when continued life is not demanded by
consideration of others. If, however, we reject the permissibility of active euthanasia,
we are effectively denying that right to those who are so disabled that they cannot
take their own lives, even with assistance from others. In order for those people to es-
cape from an intolerable existence, it is necessary for someone else to kill them. If we
forbid others to kill them, when there are others who are willing to do so, we are ex-
acerbating the already quite terrible hardships these people have had to bear. Thus
some advocates of the rights of the disabled have claimed, with considerable plausi-
bility, that a policy that permits suicide but forbids active euthanasia unfairly dis-
criminates against the disabled.
Despite these considerations, many people are unable to evade the nagging sense
that killing another person is fundamentally different from allowing him to die or
460 the ethics of killing
even assisting him to kill himself. Yet how can they explain why, intuitively, it seems
to make no difference whether Youk pressed the button himself or whether Kevorkian
pressed it at Youk’s request? Some philosophers have contended that cases of this
sort—in which the distinction between killing and letting die seems to have no moral
significance—show that the distinction is, in these cases and all others, devoid of sig-
nificance. They argue that, because we are wrong to suppose that the distinction has
moral significance, we must acknowledge that, in the absence of contingent differ-
ences, active euthanasia must be permissible when passive euthanasia would be—par-
ticularly in cases in which merely allowing a person to die would prolong his agony.55
I believe that there is a different and more plausible explanation of why it is no
worse for Kevorkian to press the button, thereby killing Youk, than it is for Youk to
press it himself. This explanation is compatible with, and indeed presupposes, the be-
lief that the distinction between killing and letting die is, in general, morally signifi-
cant. It assumes that, if the distinction has moral significance, that must be because it
is an instance of the more general distinction between doing and allowing. Most
people believe that a person’s actively bringing about an outcome that would not have
occurred without his intervention has a different moral significance from a person’s
allowing that outcome to occur. Perhaps the active causing of the outcome ties the
agent more closely to it, making him more responsible for it than he would have been
if it had occurred even in his absence. I will not attempt to defend any particular ex-
planation of the moral significance of the distinction between doing and allowing. If,
however, this broad distinction does have a general significance, it offers an explana-
tion of why killing is in general more seriously wrong than letting someone die. If, in
general, the mode of agency involved in actively intervening to bring about an out-
come is morally more significant than that involved in allowing an outcome to occur,
it seems that doing harm must in general be more seriously morally objectionable
than allowing harm to occur. Because death is normally harmful to those who die, it
follows that killing must in general be more seriously objectionable than letting die.
Notice, however, that the significance of the distinction between doing and allow-
ing should be reversed in cases in which the outcome is good rather than bad. If doing
harm is worse than allowing harm to occur, actively benefiting someone should, in
general, be better than merely allowing someone to be benefited, even when all other
things (such as motive, intention, cost to the agent, and so on) are equal. If that is right,
it explains why it was not worse for Kevorkian to press the button, thereby killing
Youk, than it would have been for him to have allowed Youk to die by allowing him
to press the button instead. For Youk’s death was unusual in not being harmful to him.
It was instead beneficial; hence, if benefiting someone is better than merely allowing
him to be benefited (for example, allowing him to benefit himself), Kevorkian’s ac-
tively bringing about that death was, if anything, better or more praiseworthy than
merely allowing or enabling Youk to bring it about would have been.
Because, in cases of euthanasia, death is beneficial rather than harmful, active eu-
thanasia should in general be better or more imperative than passive euthanasia.56 To
suppose otherwise is to divorce the distinction between killing and letting die from
its source in the distinction between doing and allowing, and to treat the general pro-
scription of killing as a taboo rather than as a rational moral requirement to which
there are intelligible exceptions. It is, of course, desirable that each of us should be
Endings 461
profoundly averse to killing other human beings and that this aversion should be sed-
ulously inculcated as a fundamental element of each person’s moral education. But
the aversion should retain its grounding in the reasons we have for refraining from
killing; it should not degenerate into an indiscriminate squeamishness. If, for example,
the reason not to kill persons derives from a requirement of respect for persons, we
should seek to prevent our aversion to wrongful killing from spilling over into cases in
which killing is compatible with, and perhaps even required by, respect for a person. I
will consider presently whether voluntary active euthanasia is a case of this sort.
The argument from suicide to euthanasia starts from cases in which suicide is
both prudentially and morally justified. Often, of course, suicide is either pruden-
tially or morally unjustified, or both. A great many people commit suicide in the mis-
taken belief that their lives are not or will not be worth living. This is an easy mistake
to make: one’s predictions about the character and content of one’s future life may be
faulty; and, even if they are accurate, one may inadequately imagine what such a life
would be like or fail to appreciate one’s ability to adapt oneself to it. Thus even if one
accepts that suicide and euthanasia can in principle be justified, one should recognize
that there will be cases in which it will be justified to restrain a person from commit-
ting suicide, or to deny a person’s request for assistance in committing suicide or for
“euthanasia,” on the ground that the person is mistaken in believing that his life is
worth not living. The difficulty of discriminating between these cases and those in
which the person’s life is genuinely not worth living is, of course, one of the major
problems with accepting the legitimacy of assisted suicide and euthanasia.
Let us, however, confine our attention to cases in which it is true, and all those in-
volved can agree that it is true, that a person’s life is worth not living. Even in these
cases, suicide or euthanasia may be unjustified because of its effects on others. There
are individual cases in which a person’s death would be so harmful to others that the
person ought morally to endure a miserable existence for the sake of those others.
These cases are, however, comparatively rare. For those who care enough about a
person to be devastated by his death are normally motivated by love to give that per-
son’s interests priority over their own. Still, there remain some cases in which a pru-
dentially rational suicide is morally unjustified because of its effects on others—for
example, a suicide by a single parent that …
Flexibility
..._
Flexibility allows the safe use of a
wide range of movements.
Flexibility is an essential part oftraining because it allows us to use a wide
range ofmovements safely. In some sports such as gymnastics, flexibility is
high on the list oftraining priorities. Coaches ofsuch sports have their own
methods of assessing improvements in flexibility. Comprehensive and
reproducible assessment is difficult to achieve, however, because ofthe
complex nature ofmovement. Nevertheless, carefully controlled
measurements, albeit in limited ranges ofmovements, can be used to assess
flexibility with a simple set ofgoniometers. It is particularly important that
the measurements are standardised and that in longitudinal studies the
same person performs all the measurements. The results can contribute
useful information in assessing overall fitness when this strict code of
practice is followed.
Conclusion
Clyde Williams is professor of sports science at the
University ofLoughborough.
The ABC of Sports Medicine has been edited by Greg
McLatchie, visitingprofessor ofsports medicine and surgical
sciences at the University ofSunderland, consultant surgeon
at Hartlepool General Hospital, and director ofthe National
Sports Medicine Institute, London.
Fitness is a complex physiological characteristic that is difficult to
describe comprehensively. Nevertheless, we can assess the central elements
of fitness in reliable and reproducible ways. Through assessing athletes
fitness we can extend health care by advising them on their ability to cope
with the exercise demands of their chosen sport.
The photographs of the javelin thrower (Tessa Sanderson) and of the woman gymnast-
(Jackie Brady) were taken by Supersport Photographs.
Imperial College of
Science, Technology and
Medicine,
London SW7 INA
Raanan Gillon, visiting
professor ofmedical ethics
BMY 1994;309:184-8
Medical ethics: four principles plus attention to scope
Raanan Gillon
The four principles plus scope approach provides
a simple, accessible, and culturally neutral approach
to thinking about ethical issues in health care. The
approach, developed in the United States, is based
on four common, basic prima facie moral commit-
ments-respect for autonomy, beneficence, non-
maleficence, and justice-plus concern for their
scope of application. It offers a common, basic
moral analytical framework and a common, basic
moral language. Although they do not provide
ordered rules, these principles can help doctors and
other health care workers to make decisions when
reflecting on moral issues that arise at work.
Nine years ago the BMJ allowed me to introduce to its
readers an approach to medical ethics developed by
the Americans Beauchamp and Childress, which is
based on four prima facie moral principles and attention
to these principles scope of application. Since then I
have often been asked for a summary of this approach
by doctors and other health care workers who find it
helpful for organising their thoughts about medical
ethics. This paper, based on the preface of a large
multiauthor textbook on medical ethics,3 offers a brief
account of this four principles plus scope approach.
The four principles plus scope approach claims that
whatever our personal philosophy, politics, religion,
moral theory, or life stance, we will find no difficulty
in committing ourselves to four prima facie moral
principles plus a reflective concern about their scope of
application. Moreover, these four principles, plus
attention to their scope of application, encompass most
of the moral issues that arise in health care.
The four prima facie principles are respect for
autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, and justice.
Prima facie, a term introduced by the English
philosopher W D Ross, means that the principle is
binding unless it conflicts with another moral principle
-if it does we have to choose between them. The four
principles approach does not provide a method for
choosing, which is a source of dissatisfaction to people
who suppose that ethics merely comprises a set of
ordered rules and that once the relevant information is
fed into an algorithm or computer out will pop the
answer. What the principles plus scope approach
can provide, however, is a common set of moral
commitments, a common moral language, and a
common set of moral issues. We should consider these
in each case before coming to our own answer using our
preferred moral theory or other approach to choose
between these principles when they conflict.
Respect for autonomy
Autonomy-literally, self rule, but probably better
described as deliberated self rule-is a special attribute
184 BMJ VOLUME 309 16 JULY 1994
of all moral agents. If we have autonomy we can make
our own decisions on the basis of deliberation; some-
times we can intend to do things as a result of those
decisions; and sometimes we can do those things to
implement the decisions (what I previously described
as autonomy of thought, of will or intention, and of
action). Respect for autonomy is the moral obligation
to respect the autonomy of others in so far as such
respect is compatible with equal respect for the
autonomy of all potentially affected. Respect for
autonomy is also sometimes described, in Kantian
terms, as treating others as ends in themselves and
never merely as means-one of Kants formulations of
his categorical imperative.
In health care respecting peoples autonomy has
many prima facie implications. It requires us to consult
people and obtain their agreement before we do things
to them-hence the obligation to obtain informed
consent from patients before we do things to try to help
them. Medical confidentiality is another implication of
respecting peoples autonomy. We do not have any
general obligation to keep other peoples secrets, but
health care workers explicitly or implicitly promise
their patients and clients that they will keep confidential
the information confided to them. Keeping promises is
a way of respecting peoples autonomy; an aspect of
running our own life depends on being able to rely on
the promises made to us by others. Without such
promises of confidentiality patients are also far less
likely to divulge the often highly private and sensitive
information that is needed for their optimal care;
thus maintaining confidentiality not only respects
patients autonomy but also increases the likelihood of
our being able to help them.
Respect for autonomy also requires us not to deceive
each other (except in circumstances in which deceit is
agreed to be permissible, such as when playing poker)
as the absence of deceit is part of the implicit agreement
among moral agents when they communicate with each
other. They organise their lives on the assumption that
people will not deceive them; their autonomy is
infringed if they are deceived. Respect for patients
autonomy prima facie requires us, therefore, not to
deceive patients, for example, about their diagnosed
illness unless they clearly wish to be deceived. Respect
for autonomy even requires us to be on time for
appointments as an agreed appointment is a kind of
mutual promise and if we do not keep an appointment
we break the promise.
To exercise respect for autonomy health care workers
must be able to communicate well with their patients
and clients. Good communication requires, most
importantly, listening (and not just with the ears) as
well as telling (and not just with the lips or a
wordprocessor) and is usually necessary for giving
patients adequate information about any proposed
intervention and for finding out whether patients want
that intervention. Good communication is also usually
necessary for finding out when patients do not want a
lot of information; some patients do not want to be told
about a bad prognosis or to participate in deciding
which of several treatments to have, preferring to leave
this decision to their doctors. Respecting such attitudes
shows just as much respect for a patients autonomy as
does giving patients information that they do want. In
my experience, however, most patients want more not
less information and want to participate in deciding
their medical care.
Beneficence and non-maleficence
Whenever we try to help others we inevitably risk
harming them; health care workers, who are committed
to helping others, must therefore consider the prin-
ciples of beneficence and non-maleficence together and
aim at producing net benefit over harm. None the less,
we must keep the two principles separate for those
circumstances in which we have or recognise no
obligation of beneficence to others (as we still have an
obligation not to harm them). Thus the traditional
Hippocratic moral obligation of medicine is to provide
net medical benefit to patients with minimal harm-
that is, beneficence with non-maleficence. To achieve
these moral objectives health care workers are com-
mitted to a wide range ofprima facie obligations.
We need to ensure that we can provide the benefits
we profess (thus professional) to be able to provide.
Hence we need rigorous and effective education and
training both before and during our professional lives.
We also need to make sure that we are offering each
patient net benefit. Interestingly, to do this we must
respect the patients autonomy for what constitutes
benefit for one patient may be harm for another. For
example, a mastectomy may constitute a prospective
net benefit for one woman with breast cancer, while for
another the destruction of an aspect of her feminine
identity may be so harmful that it cannot be outweighed
even by the prospect of an extended life expectancy.
The obligation to provide net benefit to patients also
requires us to be clear about risk and probability when
we make our assessments of harm and benefit. Clearly,
a low probability of great harm such as death or severe
disability is of less moral importance in the context of
non-maleficence than is a high probability of such
harm, and a high probability of great benefit such as
cure of a life threatening disease is of more moral
importance in the context of beneficence than is a
low probability of such benefit. We therefore need
empirical information about the probabilities of the
various harms and benefits that may result from
proposed health care interventions. This information
has to come from effective medical research, which is
also therefore a prima facie moral obligation. The
obligation to produce net benefit, however, also
requires us to define whose benefit and whose harms
are likely to result from a proposed intervention. This
problem of moral scope is particularly important in
medical research and population medicine.
One moral concept that in recent years has become
popular in health care is that of empowerment-that is,
doing things to help patients and clients to be more in
control of their health and health care. Sometimes
empowerment is even proposed as a new moral
obligation. On reflection I think that empowerment is,
however, essentially an action that combines the two
moral obligations of beneficence and respect for
autonomy to help patients in ways that not only respect
but also enhance their autonomy.
Justice
The fourth prima facie moral principle is justice.
Justice is often regarded as being synonymous with
fairness and can be summarised as the moral obligation
to act on the basis of fair adjudication between
competing claims. In health care ethics I have found it
useful to subdivide obligations of justice into three
categories: fair distribution of scarce resources
(distributive justice), respect for peoples rights (rights
based justice) and respect for morally acceptable laws
(legal justice).
Equality is at the heart of justice, but, as Aristotle
argued so long ago, justice is more than mere equality
-people can be treated unjustly even if they are
treated equally.45 He argued that it was important to
treat equals equally (what health economists are
increasingly calling horizontal equity) and to treat
unequals unequally in proportion to the morally
relevant inequalities (vertical equity). People have
argued ever since about the morally relevant criteria for
BMJ VOLUME 309 16 JULY 1994 185
regarding and treating people as equals and those for
regarding and treating them as unequals. The debate
flourishes in moral, religious, philosophical, and
political contexts, and we are no closer to agreement
than we were in Aristotles time.
Pending such agreement health care workers need to
tread warily as we have no special justification for
imposing our own personal or professional views about
justice on others. We certainly need to recognise
and acknowledge the competing moral concerns. For
example, in the context of the allocation of resources
conflicts exist between several common moral concerns:
to provide sufficient health care to meet the needs of all
who need it; when this is impossible, to distribute
health care resources in proportion to the extent of
peoples needs for health care; to allow health care
workers to give priority to the needs of their
patients; to provide equal access to health care; to allow
people as much choice as possible in selecting their
health care; to maximise the benefit produced by the
available resources; to respect the autonomy of the
people who provide those resources and thus to limit
the cost to taxpayers and subscribers to health insurance
schemes. All these criteria for justly allocating health
care resources can be morally justified but not all can be
fully met simultaneously.
Similar moral conflicts arise in the context of rights
based justice and legal justice.
PERSONAL DECISION MAKING
The best moral strategy for justice that I have found
for myself as a health care worker is first to distinguish
whether it is I or an organisation, profession, or society
itself that has to make a decision. For example, how
should I respond to a particular patient who wants an
abortion? is distinct from, what is this hospitals
organisational view on abortion? and what is the
medical professions collective view on abortion? and
what is societys view as expressed in law and
practice?
Firstly, for decisions that I must take myself
I must try to exclude decisions that have no moral basis
or justification. Neither pursuit of my own self interest
-for example, accepting bribes from patients,
hospitals, or drug manufacturers-nor action that
discriminates against patients on the basis of personal
preference or prejudice can provide a just or morally
acceptable basis for allocating scarce health care
resources or for any other category ofjustice. Moreover,
it is not my role as a doctor to punish patients;
withholding antibiotics from smokers who do not give
up smoking or refusing to refer heavy drinkers with
liver damage induced by alcohol for specialist assess-
ment on the grounds that they are at fault is not a just
or morally acceptable basis for rationing my medical
resources.
Secondly, I should not waste the resources at my
disposal; so if a cheaper drug is likely to produce as
much benefit as a more expensive one I should
prescribe the cheaper one. Cost and its team mate
opportunity cost are moral issues and central to
distributive justice. If I believe, however, that an
expensive drug is clearly and significantly better for my
patient than a cheaper alternative and I am allowed
to prescribe it then I believe that I should do so.
Thus, like many British general practitioners, I try
oxytetracycline first when treating acne, but if it
does not work well I prescribe the more expensive
minocycline; for depression I usually start with tri-
cyclic antidepressants, but if they do not work well
or the side effects are unacceptable I prescribe the new
and expensive 5-hydroxytryptamine uptake inhibitors.
Thirdly, I should respect patients rights. For
example, my disapproval of a patients lifestyle would
not be a morally acceptable justification for refusing to
provide a certificate of sickness ifhe or she cannot work
because of sickness. I have no special privilege as a
health care worker, however, to create societal rights
for my patients. For example, while I might think that
all my unemployed patients should receive sickness
benefit, in Britain they have a right to receive it only if
they cannot work because of sickness; I have a right,
therefore, to provide a certificate of sickness only if this
is the case.
Fourthly, I ought to obey morally acceptable laws.
Thus, even though I may disapprove of breaking a
patients confidence, if he or she has one of several
infectious diseases I am legally obliged to notify the
relevant authorities. If I believe that the law is morally
unjustified I am morally entitled to break the law; but
this gives me no legal entitlement to break the law,
and I should be prepared to face the legal consequences
of disobeying it. I should also decide exactly what I
mean by a morally unjustified law. I suggest, though
here do not argue, that it is the processes through
which laws are enacted that confer moral legitimacy
not the content of the laws. Thus if a law is enacted
through a democratic political system-and hence
one that fundamentally respects autonomy-which
represents conflicting views within its population and
makes laws on the basis of certain common moral
values that reflect the four principles then that law is
morally acceptable, and prima facie we are morally
required to obey it.
ORGANISATIONAL, PROFESSIONAL, AND SOCIETAL
DECISIONS
My role in taking decisions about justice that are
organisational, professional, or societal should only be
as a member of the relevant organisation, profession,
or society. It is therefore morally consistent to pursue
at different levels objectives that are mutually in-
consistent. The medical directorate at the hospital
where I work may have decided to prohibit the
prescription of a particularly expensive drug. As a
member of that directorate I may have argued in favour
of prescribing the drug in special cases, but my
arguments were rejected. It is morally proper for me as
a clinician to accept the directorates decision and act
accordingly even when faced with an exceptional case
in which I believe the expensive drug would be
preferable. It is also morally legitimate for me to point
to such cases (shroud waving) in my political role
as a member of a democratic society, arguing, for
example, for more resources for health care than, say,
for defence.
As members of society we are still feeling our way
even at the level of defining what the competing moral
concerns of justice are. We must be particularly wary
of apparently simple solutions to what have been
perceived as highly complex problems for at least
2500 years. For example, populist solutions in
distributive justice such as have occurred in Oregon
in the United States6 and technical and simplistic
economic solutions such as the system of costed quality
adjusted life years (QALYs) are tempting in their
definitiveness and simplicity; they fail, however, to
give value to the wide range of other potentially
relevant moral concerns. Until there is far greater
social agreement and understanding of these exceed-
ingly complex issues I believe it is morally safer to seek
gradual improvement in our current methods of trying
to reconcile the competing moral concerns-to seek
ways of muddling through elegantly as Hunter
advocates&-than to be seduced by systems that seek to
convert these essentially moral choices into apparently
scientific, numerical methods and formulas.
As Calabresi and Bobbitt suggested in the 1970s,
rationing scarce resources that prolong life and enhance
health often entails tragic choices-choices between
BMJ VOLUME 309 16 JULY 1994186
people and between values. Societies seek strategies to
minimise the destructive effect of such choices,
including tendencies to change their strategies over
time.9 Calabresi suggests that we are like a juggler
trying to keep too many balls in the air; like the juggler
we must do our best to improve our juggling skills to
keep more balls in the air for more of the time and to
avoid letting any ball stay on the ground for too long.
We must accept, however, that in the context of
competing and mutually incompatible claims there will
always be some balls on the ground. Moreover, we
should not be surprised that there will always be some
people dissatisfied after justice has been done because
by definition not everyones claims can be met.
Scope
We may agree about our substantive moral commit-
ments and our prima facie moral obligations of respect
for autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, and
justice, yet we may still disagree about their scope of
application-that is, we may disagree radically about
to what or to whom we owe these moral obligations.
Interesting and important theoretical issues surround
the scope of each of the four principles. We clearly do
not owe a duty of beneficence to everyone and
everything; so whom or what do we have a moral duty
to help and how much should we help them? While we
clearly have a prima facie obligation to avoid harming
everyone, who and what count as everyone? Similarly,
even if we agree that the scope of the principle of
respect for autonomy is universal, encompassing
all autonomous agents, who or what counts as an
autonomous agent?
Who or what falls within the scope of our obligation
to distribute scarce resources fairly according to the
principle of justice? Is it everyone in the world? Future
people? Just people in our own countries? And who or
what has rights? Do plants have rights? Does the
environment have rights? Does a work of art have
rights? Do animals have rights and if so, which
animals? Conversely, against whom may holders of
rights claim the correlative moral obligation? Similar
questions concern the scope of legal justice.
SCOPE FOR HEALTH CARE WORKERS
Fortunately for health care workers some of these
issues of scope have been clarified for them by their
special relationship with their patients or clients. In
particular, the controversial issue of who falls within
the scope of beneficence is answered unambiguously
for at least one category of people: all health care
workers have a moral obligation to help their patients
and clients. Patients or clients fall within the scope of
the health care workers duty of beneficence. This
fact is established by the personal and professional
commitments of the health care professionals and their
organisations-they all profess a commitment to help
their patients and clients, and to do so with minimal
harm. This commitment is underwritten by the
societies in which they practise, both informally and
through legal rules and regulations that define the
health care professionals duties of care.
Two issues of scope are of particular practical
importance for health care workers. The first is the
question ofwho falls within the scope of the prima facie
principle of respect for autonomy. The second is
the question of what is the scope of the widely
acknowledged right to life; who and what has a right
to life?
Obviously the scope of the principle of respect for
autonomy must include autonomous agents-we
cannot respect the autonomy of a boot or anything else
that is not autonomous. But who or what counts as an
autonomous agent? When we disagree about whether
or not to respect the decision of a girl of 14 to take the
oral contraceptive pill we are in effect disagreeing
about the scope of application of the principle of
respect for autonomy.
Similar questions about the scope of respect for
autonomy arise in other paediatric contexts, in the care
of severely mentally ill or mentally impaired people,
and in the care of elderly people who are severely
mentally impaired. Some patients clearly do not fall
within the scope of respect for autonomy; newborn
babies, for example, are not autonomous agents as
autonomy requires the capacity to deliberate. But 7
year olds usually can deliberate to a degree. How much
capacity for logical thought and deliberation and what
other attributes are required for somebody to be
an adequately autonomous agent? Possible other,
necessary attributes include an adequately extensive
and accurate knowledge base, including that born of
experience and of accurte perception, on which to
deliberate; an ability to conceive of and reflect on
ourselves over time, both past and future; an ability to
reason hypothetically-what if reasoning; an ability
to defer gratification for ourselves as an aspect of self
rule; and sufficient will power for self rule.
However these philosophical questions are an-
swered, health care workers increasingly acknowledge
that the autonomy of even young children and severely
mentally impaired people should prima facie be
respected unless there are good moral reasons not to do
so. Moreover, those reasons will depend highly on the
context; a young child or a severely mentally impaired
person may not be autonomous enough to have his or
her decision to reject an operation respected but be
autonomous enough to decide what food to eat or
clothes to wear. When patients who are not adequately
autonomous for all their decisions to be respected make
decisions that seem to be against their ifiterests then
important issues arise about who should be regarded as
appropriate to make decisions on their behalf and
about the criteria that they should use to do so.
The second important issue of scope for health care
workers concerns the right to life. Who or what has
this right to life? To answer the question we have
to determine what is meant by the right to life.
Specifically, is it simply the right not to be unjustly
killed or does it also include a right to be kept alive?
The scope of the first right will clearly be greater than
the scope of the latter: we have prima facie moral
obligations not to kill all people but we have obligations
to keep alive only some people. Even with the first
definition of the right to life (a right not to be unjustly
killed) a question of scope arises; although all people
clearly fall within its scope, do (non-human) animals?
And what do we mean by people? In response to
this last question much debate, often extremely
acrimonious, occurs in health care ethics over the right
to life of human embryos, fetuses, newborn babies,
and patients who are permanently unconscious or even
brain dead.
It is salutary to reflect that these contentious issues
are not about the content of our moral obligations but
about to whom and what we owe them-that is, they
are questions about the scope of our agreed moral
obligations. Our answers are reasoned and carefully
argued but deeply conflicting, either religiously or
philosophically. Such disagreement about scope does
not justify accusing those who disagree with us of
bad faith or incompatible moral standards; in principle
it is open to resolution within our shared moral
commitment.
Conclusion
The four principles plus scope approach is clearly
not without its critics. And the approach does not
BMJ VOLUME 309 16 JULY 1994
Pursuit ofjustice-keeping all
the balls in the air
purport to offer a method of dealing with conflicts
between the principles. But I have not found anyone
who seriously argues that he or she cannot accept any
of these prima facie principles or found plausible
examples of concerns about health care ethics that
require additional moral principles.
The four principles plus scope approach enables
health care workers from totally disparate moral
cultures to share a fairly basic, common moral commit-
ment, common moral language, and common analytical
framework for reflecting on problems in health care
ethics. Such an approach, which is neutral between
competing religious, political, cultural, and philo-
sophical theories, can be shared by everyone regardless
of their background. It is surely too important a moral
prize to be rejected carelessly or ignorantly; for the
sake of mere opposition; or for the fun of being a
philosophical Socratic gadfly.
1 Gillon R. Philosophical medical ethics. Chichester: Wiley, 1986. (From a 26 part
series in BMJ from 1985;290: 1117-9 to 1986;292:543-5.)
2 Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics. 3rd ed. New York,
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989.
3 Gillon R, Lloyd A, eds. Principles ofhealth care ethics. Chichester: Wiley, 1994.
4 Aristotle. Nichomachean ethics. Book 5. McKeon R, ed. The basic works of
Aristotle. New York: Random House, 1941.
5 Aristotle. Politics. Book 3, chapter 9. McKeon R, ed. The basic works of
Aristotle. New York: Random House, 1941.
6 Klein R. On the Oregon trail: rationing health care-more politics than science.
BMJ 1991;302:1-2.
7 Williams A. Economics, society and health care ethics. In: Gillon R, Lloyd A,
eds. Principles ofhealth care ethics. Chichester: Wiley, 1994:829-42.
8 Hunter DJ. Rationing dilemmas in health care. Birmingham: National Association
ofHealth Authorities and Trusts, 1993. (NAHAT research paper No 8.)
9 Calabresi G, Bobbitt P. Tragic choices. New York: Norton, 1978.
(Accepted 16March 1994)
This is the seventh in a series of
occasional notes on medical
statistics.
Medical Statistics
Laboratory, Imperial
Cancer Research Fund,
London WC2A 3PX
Douglas G Altman, head
Department ofPublic
Health Sciences, St
Georges Hospital Medical
School, London
SW17 IRE
J Martin Bland, reader in
medical statistics
BMJ 1994309:188
Statistics Notes
Diagnostic tests 3: receiver operating characteristic plots
Douglas G Altman, J Martin Bland
We have previously considered diagnosis based on
tests that give a …
$�HIHQVH�RI�$ERUWLRQ
$XWKRU�V���-XGLWK�-DUYLV�7KRPVRQ
6RXUFH��3KLORVRSK\� �3XEOLF�$IIDLUV��9RO�����1R�����$XWXPQ���������SS�������
3XEOLVKHG�E\��:LOH\
6WDEOH�85/��http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265091 .
$FFHVVHG������������������
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]
.
Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy &Public Affairs.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265091?origin=JSTOR-pdf
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JUDITH JARVIS THOMSON A Defense of Abortion
Most opposition to abortion relies on the premise that the fetus is a
human being, a person, from the moment of conception. The premise
is argued for, but, as I think, not well. Take, for example, the most
common argument. We are asked to notice that the development of
a human being from conception through birth into childhood is con-
tinuous; then it is said that to draw a line, to choose a point in this
development and say before this point the thing is not a person, after
this point it is a person is to make an arbitrary choice, a choice for
which in the nature of things no good reason can be given. It is con-
cluded that the fetus is, or anyway that we had better say it is, a per-
son from the moment of conception. But this conclusion does not fol-
low. Similar things might be said about the development of an acorn
into an oak tree, and it does not follow that acorns are oak trees, or
that we had better say they are. Arguments of this form are sometimes
called slippery slope arguments-the phrase is perhaps self-explana-
tory-and it is dismaying that opponents of abortion rely on them so
heavily and uncritically.
I am inclined to agree, however, that the prospects for drawing a
line in the development of the fetus look dim. I am inclined to think
also that we shall probably have to agree that the fetus has already
become a human person well before birth. Indeed, it comes as a sur-
prise when one first learns how early in its life it begins to acquire
human characteristics. By the tenth week, for example, it already has
i. I am very much indebted to James Thomson for discussion, criticism, and
many helpful suggestions.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
48 Philosophy & Public Affairs
a face, arms and legs, fingers and toes; it has internal organs, and
brain activity is detectable.2 On the other hand, I think that the prem-
ise is false, that the fetus is not a person from the moment of con-
ception. A newly fertilized ovum, a newly implanted clump of cells, is
no more a person than an acorn is an oak tree. But I shall not discuss
any of this. For it seems to me to be of great interest to ask what
happens if, for the sake of argument, we allow the premise. How, pre-
cisely, are we supposed to get from there to the conclusion that abor-
tion is morally impermissible? Opponents of abortion commonly
spend most of their time establishing that the fetus is a person, and
hardly any time explaining the step from there to the impermissibility
of abortion. Perhaps they think the step too simple and obvious to
require much comment. Or perhaps instead they are simply being eco-
nomical in argument. Many of those who defend abortion rely on the
premise that the fetus is not a person, but only a bit of tissue that
will become a person at birth; and why pay out more arguments than
you have to? Whatever the explanation, I suggest that the step they
take is neither easy nor obvious, that it calls for closer examination
than it is commonly given, and that when we do give it this closer
examination we shall feel inclined to reject it.
I propose, then, that we grant that the fetus is a person. from the
moment of conception. How does the argument go from here? Some-
thing like this, I take it. Every person has a right to life. So the fetus
has a right to life. No doubt the mother has a right to decide what
shall happen in and to her body; everyone would grant that. But surely
a persons right to life is stronger and more stringent than the mothers
right to decide what happens in and to her body, and so outweighs it.
So the fetus may not be killed; an abortion may not be performed.
It sounds plausible. But now let me ask you to imagine this. You
wake up in the morning and find yourself back to back in bed with
an unconscious violinist. A famous unconscious violinist. He has been
found to have a fatal kidney ailment, and the Society of Music Lovers
2. Daniel Callahan, Abortion: Law, Choice and Morality (New York, 1970),
p. 373. This book gives a fascinating survey of the available information on
abortion. The Jewish tradition is surveyed in David M. Feldman, Birth Control in
Jewish Law (New York, i968), Part 5, the Catholic tradition in John T. Noonan,
Jr., An Almost Absolute Value in History, in The Morality of Abortion, ed. John
T. Noonan, Jr. (Cambridge, Mass., 1970).
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
49 A Defense of Abortion
has canvassed all the available medical records and found that you
alone have the right blood type to help. They have therefore kidnapped
you, and last night the violinists circulatory system was plugged into
yours, so that your kidneys can be used to extract poisons from his
blood as well as your own. The director of the hospital now tells you,
Look, were sorry the Society of Music Lovers did this to you-we
would never have permitted it if we had known. But still, they did it,
and the violinist now is plugged into you. To unplug you would be to
kill him. But never mind, its only for nine months. By then he will
have recovered from his ailment, and can safely be unplugged from
you. Is it morally incumbent on you to accede to this situation? No
doubt it would be very nice of you if you did, a great kindness. But
do you have to accede to it? What if it were not nine months, but nine
years? Or longer still? What if the director of the hospital says,
Tough luck, I agree, but youve now got to stay in bed, with the vio-
linist plugged into you, for the rest of your life. Because remember
this. All persons have a right to life, and violinists are persons. Granted
you have a right to decide what happens in and to your body, but a
persons right to life outweighs your right to decide what happens in
and to your body. So you cannot ever be unplugged from him. I
imagine you would regard this as outrageous, which suggests that
something really is wrong with that plausible-sounding argument I
mentioned a moment ago.
In this case, of course, you were kidnapped; you didnt volunteer
for the operation that plugged the violinist into your kidneys. Can
those who oppose abortion on the ground I mentioned make an excep-
tion for a pregnancy due to rape? Certainly. They can say that per-
sons have a right to life only if they didnt come into existence because
of rape; or they can say that all persons have a right to life, but that
some have less of a right to life than others, in particular, that those
who came into existence because of rape have less. But these state-
ments have a rather unpleasant sound. Surely the question of whether
you have a right to life at all, or how much of it you have, shouldnt
turn on the question of whether or not you are the product of a rape.
And in fact the people who oppose abortion on the ground I men-
tioned do not make this distinction, and hence do not make an excep-
tion in case of rape.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
50 Philosophy & Public Affairs
Nor do they make an exception for a case in which the mother has
to spend the nine months of her pregnancy in bed. They would agree
that would be a great pity, and hard on the mother; but all the same,
all persons have a right to life, the fetus is a person, and so on. I sus-
pect, in fact, that they would not make an exception for a case in
which, miraculously enough, the pregnancy went on for nine years,
or even the rest of the mothers life.
Some wont even make an exception for a case in which continua-
tion of the pregnancy is likely to shorten the mothers life; they regard
abortion as impermissible even to save the mothers life. Such cases
are nowadays very rare, and many opponents of abortion do not accept
this extreme view. All the same, it is a good place to begin: a number
of points of interest come out in respect to it.
i. Let us call the view that abortion is impermissible even to save
the mothers life the extreme view. I want to suggest first that it does
not issue from the argument I mentioned earlier without the addition
of some fairly powerful premises. Suppose a woman has become preg-
nant, and now learns that she has a cardiac condition such that she
will die if she carries the baby to term. What may be done for her?
The fetus, being a person, has a right to life, but as the mother is a
person too, so has she a right to life. Presumably they have an equal
right to life. How is it supposed to come out that an abortion may
not be performed? If mother and child have an equal right to life,
shouldnt we perhaps flip a coin? Or should we add to the mothers
right to life her right to decide what happens in and to her body,
which everybody seems to be ready to grant-the sum of her rights
now outweighing the fetus right to life?
The most familiar argument here is the following. We are told that
performing the abortion would be directly killing3 the child, whereas
doing nothing would not be killing the mother, but only letting her
die. Moreover, in killing the child, one would be killing an innocent
person, for the child has committed no crime, and is not aiming at
his mothers death. And then there are a variety of ways in which this
3. The term direct in the arguments I refer to is a technical one. Roughly,
what is meant by direct killing is either killing as an end in itself, or killing
as a means to some end, for example, the end of saving someone elses life. See
note 6, below, for an example of its use.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
51 A Defense of Abortion
might be continued. (i) But as directly killing an innocent person is
always and absolutely impermissible, an abortion may not be per-
formed. Or, (2) as directly killing an innocent person is murder, and
murder is always and absolutely impermissible, an abortion may not
be performed.4 Or, (3) as ones duty to refrain from directly killing an
innocent person is more stringent than ones duty to keep a person
from dying, an abortion may not be performed. Or, (4) if ones only
options are, directly killing an innocent person or letting a person die,
one must prefer letting the person die, and thus an abortion may not
be performed.5
Some people seem to have thought that these are not further prem-
ises which must be added if the conclusion is to be reached, but that
they follow from the very fact that an innocent person has a right to
life.6 But this seems to me to be a mistake, and perhaps the simplest
way to show this is to bring out that while we must certainly grant
that innocent persons have a right to life, the theses in (i) through
(4) are all false. Take (2), for example. If directly killing an inno-
cent person is murder, and thus is impermissible, then the mothers
directly killing the innocent person inside her is murder, and thus is
4. Cf. Encyclical Letter of Pope Pius XI on Christian Marriage, St. Paul Edi-
tions (Boston, n.d.), p. 32: however much we may pity the mother whose health
and even life is gravely imperiled in the performance of the duty allotted to her
by nature, nevertheless what could ever be a sufficient reason for excusing in any
way the direct murder of the innocent? This is precisely what we are dealing
with here. Noonan (The Morality of Abortion, p. 43) reads this as follows:
What cause can ever avail to excuse in any way the direct killing of the inno-
cent? For it is a question of that.
5. The thesis in (4) is in an interesting way weaker than those in (i), (2),
and (3): they rule out abortion even in cases in which both mother and child
will die if the abortion is not performed. By contrast, one who held the view
expressed in (4) could consistently say that one neednt prefer letting two per-
sons die to killing one.
6. Cf. the following passage from Pius XII, Address to the Italian Catholic
Society of Midwives: The baby in the maternal breast has the right to life imme-
diately from God.-Hence there is no man, no human authority, no science, no
medical, eugenic, social, economic or moral indication which can establish or
grant a valid juridical ground for a direct deliberate disposition of an innocent
human life, that is a disposition which looks to its destruction either as an end
or as a means to another end perhaps in itself not illicit.-The baby, still not
born, is a man in the same degree and for the same reason as the mother
(quoted in Noonan, The Morality of Abortion, p. 45).
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
52 Philosophy & Public Affairs
impermissible. But it cannot seriously be thought to be murder if the
mother performs an abortion on herself to save her life. It cannot
seriously be said that she must refrain, that she must sit passively by
and wait for her death. Let us look again at the case of you and the
violinist. There you are, in bed with the violinist, and the director of
the hospital says to you, Its all most distressing, and I deeply sym-
pathize, but you see this is putting an additional strain on your kid-
neys, and youll be dead within the month. But you have to stay where
you are all the same. Because unplugging you would be directly kill-
ing an innocent violinist, and thats murder, and thats impermissi-
ble. If anything in the world is true, it is that you do not commit
murder, you do not do what is impermissible, if you reach around to
your back and unplug yourself from that violinist to save your life.
The main focus of attention in writings on abortion has been on
what a third party may or may not do in answer to a request from a
woman for an abortion. This is in a way understandable. Things being
as they are, there isnt much a woman can safely do to abort herself.
So the question asked is what a third party may do, and what the
mother may do, if it is mentioned at all, is deduced, almost as an after-
thought, from what it is concluded that third parties may do. But it
seems to me that to treat the matter in this way is to refuse to grant
to the mother that very status of person which is so firmly insisted on
for the fetus. For we cannot simply read off what a person may do
from what a third party may do. Suppose you find yourself trapped
in a tiny house with a growing child. I mean a very tiny house, and a
rapidly growing child-you are already up against the wall of the
house and in a few minutes youll be crushed to death. The child on
the other hand wont be crushed to death; if nothing is done to stop
him from growing hell be hurt, but in the end hell simply burst open
the house and walk out a free man. Now I could well understand it
if a bystander were to say, Theres nothing we can do for you. We
cannot choose between your life and his, we cannot be the ones to
decide who is to live, we cannot intervene. But it cannot be concluded
that you too can do nothing, that you cannot attack it to save your
life. However innocent the child may be, you do not have to wait pas-
sively while it crushes you to death. Perhaps a pregnant woman is
vaguely felt to have the status of house, to which we dont allow the
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
53 A Defense of Abortion
right of self-defense. But if the woman houses the child, it should be
remembered that she is a person who houses it.
1 should perhaps stop to say explicitly that I am not claiming that
people have a right to do anything whatever to save their lives. I think,
rather, that there are drastic limits to the right of self-defense. If
someone threatens you with death unless you torture someone else
to death, I think you have not the right, even to save your life, to do
so. But the case under consideration here is very different. In our case
there are only two people involved, one whose life is threatened, and
one who threatens it. Both are innocent: the one who is threatened is
not threatened because of any fault, the one who threatens does not
threaten because of any fault. For this reason we may feel that we
bystanders cannot intervene. But the person threatened can.
In sum, a woman surely can defend her life against the threat to
it posed by the unborn child, even if doing so involves its death. And
this shows not merely that the theses in (i) through (4) are false; it
shows also that the extreme view of abortion is false, and so we need
not canvass any other possible ways of arriving at it from the argu-
ment I mentioned at the outset.
2. The extreme view could of course be weakened to say that while
abortion is permissible to save the mothers life, it may not be per-
formed by a third party, but only by the mother herself. But this can-
not be right either. For what we have to keep in mind is that the
mother and the unborn child are not like two tenants in a small house
which has, by an unfortunate mistake, been rented to both: the
mother owns the house. The fact that she does adds to the offensive-
ness of deducing that the mother can do nothing from the supposition
that third parties can do nothing. But it does more than this: it casts
a bright light on the supposition that third parties can do nothing.
Certainly it lets us see that a third party who says I cannot choose
between you is fooling himself if he thinks this is impartiality. If
Jones has found and fastened on a certain coat, which he needs to
keep him from freezing, but which Smith also needs to keep him from
freezing, then it is not impartiality that says I cannot choose between
you when Smith owns the coat. Women have said again and again
This body is my body! and they have reason to feel angry, reason to
feel that it has been like shouting into the wind. Smith, after all, is
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
54 Philosophy & Public Affairs
hardly likely to bless us if we say to him, Of course its your coat,
anybody would grant that it is. But no one may choose between you
and Jones who is to have it.
We should really ask what it is that says no one may choose in
the face of the fact that the body that houses the child is the mothers
body. It may be simply a failure to appreciate this fact. But it may be
something more interesting, namely the sense that one has a right to
refuse to lay hands on people, even where it would be just and fair to
do so, even where justice seems to require that somebody do so. Thus
justice might call for somebody to get Smiths coat back from Jones,
and yet you have a right to refuse to be the one to lay hands on Jones,
a right to refuse to do physical violence to him. This, I think, must be
granted. But then what should be said is not no one may choose,
but only I cannot choose, and indeed not even this, but I will not
act, leaving it open that somebody else can or should, and in particu-
lar that anyone in a position of authority, with the job of securing
peoples rights, both can and should. So this is no difficulty. I have
not been arguing that any given third party must accede to the moth-
ers request that he perform an abortion to save her life, but only that
he may.
I suppose that in some views of human life the mothers body is only
on loan to her, the loan not being one which gives her any prior claim
to it. One who held this view might well think it impartiality to say
I cannot choose. But I shall simply ignore this possibility. My own
view is that if a human being has any just, prior claim to anything at
all, he has a just, prior claim to his own body. And perhaps this
neednt be argued for here anyway, since, as I mentioned, the argu-
ments against abortion we are looking at do grant that the woman
has a right to decide what happens in and to her body.
But although they do grant it, I have tried to show that they do not
take seriously what is done in granting it. I suggest the same thing
will reappear even more clearly when we turn away from cases in
which the mothers life is at stake, and attend, as I propose we now
do, to the vastly more common cases in which a woman wants an
abortion for some less weighty reason than preserving her own life.
3. Where the mothers life is not at stake, the argument I men-
tioned at the outset seems to have a much stronger pull. Everyone
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
55 A Defense of Abortion
has a right to life, so the unborn person has a right to life. And isnt
the childs right to life weightier than anything other than the moth-
ers own right to life, which she might put forward as ground for an
abortion?
This argument treats the right to life as if it were unproblematic.
It is not, and this seems to me to be precisely the source of the mistake.
For we should now, at long last, ask what it comes to, to have a
right to life. In some views having a right to life includes having a
right to be given at least the bare minimum one needs for continued
life. But suppose that what in fact is the bare minimum a man needs
for continued life is something he has no right at all to be given? If
I am sick unto death, and the only thing that will save my life is the
touch of Henry Fondas cool hand on my fevered brow, then all the
same, I have no right to be given the touch of Henry Fondas cool hand
on my fevered brow. It would be frightfully nice of him to fly in from
the West Coast to provide it. It would be less nice, though no doubt
well meant, if my friends flew out to the West Coast and carried
Henry Fonda back with them. But I have no right at all against any-
body that he should do this for me. Or again, to return to the story I
told earlier, the fact that for continued life that violinist needs the
continued use of your kidneys does not establish that he has a right
to be given the continued use of your kidneys. He certainly has no
right against you that you should give him continued use of your kid-
neys. For nobody has any right to use your kidneys unless you give
him such a right; and nobody has the right against you that you shall
give him this right-if you do allow him to go on using your kidneys,
this is a kindness on your part, and not something he can claim from
you as his due. Nor has he any right against anybody else that they
should give him continued use of your kidneys. Certainly he had no
right against the Society of Music Lovers that they should plug him
into you in the first place. And if you now start to unplug yourself,
having learned that you will otherwise have to spend nine years in
bed with him, there is nobody in the world who must try to prevent
you, in order to see to it that he is given something he has a right to
be given.
Some people are rather stricter about the right to life. In their view,
it does not include the right to be given anything, but amounts to,
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
56 Philosophy & Public Affairs
and only to, the right not to be killed by anybody. But here a related
difficulty arises. If everybody is to refrain from killing that violinist,
then everybody must refrain from doing a great many different sorts
of things. Everybody must refrain from slitting his throat, everybody
must refrain from shooting him-and everybody must refrain from
unplugging you from him. But does he have a right against everybody
that they shall refrain from unplugging you from him? To refrain
from doing this is to allow him to continue to use your kidneys. It
could be argued that he has a right against us that we should allow
him to continue to use your kidneys. That is, while he had no right
against us that we should give him the use of your kidneys, it might
be argued that he anyway has a right against us that we shall not now
intervene and deprive him of the use of your kidneys. I shall come
back to third-party interventions later. But certainly the violinist has
no right against you that you shall allow him to continue to use your
kidneys. As I said, if you do allow him to use them, it is a kindness
on your part, and not something you owe him.
The difficulty I point to here is not peculiar to the right to life. It
reappears in connection with all the other natural rights; and it is
something which an adequate account of rights must deal with. For
present purposes it is enough just to draw attention to it. But I would
stress that I am not arguing that people do not have a right to life-
quite to the contrary, it seems to me that the primary control we must
place on the acceptability of an account of rights is that it should turn
out in that account to be a truth that all persons have a right to life.
I am arguing only that having a right to life does not guarantee hav-
ing either a right to be given the use of or a right to be allowed con-
tinued use of another persons body-even if one needs it for life itself.
So the right to life will not serve the opponents of abortion in the very
simple and clear way in which they seem to have thought it would.
4. There is another way to bring out the difficulty. In the most ordi-
nary sort of case, to deprive someone of what he has a right to is to
treat him unjustly. Suppose a boy and his small brother are jointly
given a box of chocolates for Christmas. If the older boy takes the
box and refuses to give his brother any of the chocolates, he is unjust
to -him, for the brother has been given a right to half of them. But
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:20:33 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
57 A Defense of Abortion
suppose that, having learned that otherwise it means nine years in
bed with that violinist, you unplug yourself from him. You surely are
not being unjust to him, for you gave him no right to use your kid-
neys, and no one else can have given him any such right. But we have
to notice that in unplugging yourself, you are killing him; and violin-
ists, like everybody else, have a right to life, and thus in the view we
were considering just now, the right not to be killed. So here you do
what he supposedly has a right you shall not do, but you do not act
unjustly to him in doing it.
The emendation which may be made at this point is this: the right
to life consists …
-RXUQDO�RI�3KLORVRSK\��,QF�
:K\�$ERUWLRQ�LV�,PPRUDO
$XWKRU�V���RQ�0DUTXLV
6RXUFH��7KH�-RXUQDO�RI�3KLORVRSK\��9RO������1R�����$SU����������SS���������
3XEOLVKHG�E\��-RXUQDO�RI�3KLORVRSK\��,QF�
6WDEOH�85/��http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026961 .
$FFHVVHG������������������
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]
.
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal
of Philosophy.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jphil
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026961?origin=JSTOR-pdf
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
WHY ABORTION IS IMMORAL 183
WHY ABORTION IS IMMORAL
T n HE view that abortion is, with rare exceptions, seriously im-
moral has received little support in the recent philosophical
literature. No doubt most philosophers affiliated with secular
institutions of higher education believe that the anti-abortion posi-
tion is either a symptom of irrational religious dogma or a conclusion
generated by seriously confused philosophical argument. The pur-
pose of this essay is to undermine this general belief. This essay sets
out an argument that purports to show, as well as any argument in
ethics can show, that abortion is, except possibly in rare cases, seri-
ously immoral, that it is in the same moral category as killing an
innocent adult human being.
The argument is based on a major assumption. Many of the most
insightful and careful writers on the ethics of abortion-such as Joel
Feinberg, Michael Tooley, Mary Anne Warren, H. Tristram Engel-
hardt, Jr., L. W. Sumner, John T. Noonan, Jr., and Philip Devine-
believe that whether or not abortion is morally permissible stands or
falls on whether or not a fetus is the sort of being whose life it is
seriously wrong to end. The argument of this essay will assume, but
not argue, that they are correct.
Also, this essay will neglect issues of great importance to a complete
ethics of abortion. Some anti-abortionists will allow that certain
abortions, such as abortion before implantation or abortion when
the life of a woman is threatened by a pregnancy or abortion after
rape, may be morally permissible. This essay will not explore the
casuistry of these hard cases. The purpose of this essay is to develop a
general argument for the claim that the overwhelming majority of
deliberate abortions are seriously immoral.
I.
A sketch of standard anti-abortion and pro-choice arguments ex-
hibits how those arguments possess certain symmetries that explain
why partisans of those positions are so convinced of the correctness
of their own positions, why they are not successful in convincing
Feinberg, Abortion, in Matters of Life and Death: New Introductory Essays
in Moral Philosophy, Tom Regan, ed. (New York: Random House, 1986), pp.
256-293; Tooley, Abortion and Infanticide, Philosophy and Public Affairs, ii, 1
(1972):37-65, Tooley, Abortion and Infanticide (New York: Oxford, 1984); War-
ren, On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion, The Monist, I.vii, 1 (1973):43-
61; Engelhardt, The Ontology of Abortion, Ethics, lxxxiv, 3 (1974):217-234;
Sumner, Abortion and Moral Theory (Princeton: University Press, 1981); Noonan,
An Almost Absolute Value in History, in The Morality of Abortion: Legal and
Historical Perspectives, Noonan, ed. (Cambridge: Harvard, 1970); and Devine,
The Ethics of Homicide (Ithaca: Cornell, 1978).
0022-362X /89/8604/183-22 (? 1989 The Journal of Philosophy, Inc.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
184 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
their opponents, and why, to others, this issue seems to be unresolv-
able. An analysis of the nature of this standoff suggests a strategy for
surmounting it.
Consider the way a typical anti-abortionist argues. She will argue
or assert that life is present from the moment of conception or that
fetuses look like babies or that fetuses possess a characteristic such as
a genetic code that is both necessary and sufficient for being human.
Anti-abortionists seem to believe that (1) the truth of all of these
claims is quite obvious, and (2) establishing any of these claims is
sufficient to show that abortion is morally akin to murder.
A standard pro-choice strategy exhibits similarities. The pro-
choicer will argue or assert that fetuses are not persons or that
fetuses are not rational agents or that fetuses are not social beings.
Pro-choicers seem to believe that (1) the truth of any of these claims
is quite obvious, and (2) establishing any of these claims is sufficient
to show that an abortion is not a wrongful killing.
In fact, both the pro-choice and the anti-abortion claims do seem
to be true, although the it looks like a baby claim is more difficult
to establish the earlier the pregnancy. We seem to have a standoff.
How can it be resolved?
As everyone who has taken a bit of logic knows, if any of these
arguments concerning abortion is a good argument, it requires not
only some claim characterizing fetuses, but also some general moral
principle that ties a characteristic of fetuses to having or not having
the right to life or to some other moral characteristic that will gener-
ate the obligation or the lack of obligation not to end the life of a
fetus. Accordingly, the arguments of the anti-abortionist and the
pro-choicer need a bit of filling in to be regarded as adequate.
Note what each partisan will say. The anti-abortionist will claim
that her position is supported by such generally accepted moral
principles as It is always prima facie seriously wrong to take a
human life or It is always prima facie seriously wrong to end the
life of a baby. Since these are generally accepted moral principles,
her position is certainly not obviously wrong. The pro-choicer will
claim that her position is supported by such plausible moral princi-
ples as Being a person is what gives an individual intrinsic moral
worth or It is only seriously prima facie wrong to take the life of a
member of the human community. Since these are generally ac-
cepted moral principles, the pro-choice position is certainly not ob-
viously wrong. Unfortunately, we have again arrived at a standoff.
Now, how might one deal with this standoff? The standard ap-
proach is to try to show how the moral principles of ones opponent
lose their plausibility under analysis. It is easy to see how this is
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
WHY ABORTION IS IMMORAI, 185
possible. On the one hand, the anti-abortionist will defend a moral
principle concerning the wrongness of killing which tends to be
broad in scope in order that even fetuses at an early stage of preg-
nancy will fall under it. The problem with broad principles is that
they often embrace too much. In this particular instance, the princi-
ple It is always prima facie wrong to take a human life seems to
entail that it is wrong to end the existence of a living human cancer-
cell culture, on the grounds that the culture is both living and
human. Therefore, it seems that the anti-abortionists favored princi-
ple is too broad.
On the other hand, the pro-choicer wants to find a moral principle
concerning the wrongness of killing which tends to be narrow in
scope in order that fetuses will not fall under it. The problem with
narrow principles is that they often do not embrace enough. Hence,
the needed principles such as It is prima facie seriously wrong to kill
only persons or It is prima facie wrong to kill only rational agents
do not explain why it is wrong to kill infants or young children or the
severely retarded or even perhaps the severely mentally ill. There-
fore, we seem again to have a standoff. The anti-abortionist charges,
not unreasonably, that pro-choice principles concerning killing are
too narrow to be acceptable; the pro-choicer charges, not unreason-
ably, that anti-abortionist principles concerning killing are too broad
to be acceptable.
Attempts by both sides to patch up the difficulties in their posi-
tions run into further difficulties. The anti-abortionist will try to
remove the problem in her position by reformulating her principle
concerning killing in terms of human beings. Now we end up with:
It is always prima facie seriously wrong to end the life of a human
being. This principle has the advantage of avoiding the problem of
the human cancer-cell culture counterexample. But this advantage is
purchased at a high price. For although it is clear that a fetus is both
human and alive, it is not at all clear that a fetus is a human being.
There is at least something to be said for the view that something
becomes a human being only after a process of development, and
that therefore first trimester fetuses and perhaps all fetuses are not
yet human beings. Hence, the anti-abortionist, by this move, has
merely exchanged one problem for another.2
The pro-choicer fares no better. She may attempt to find reasons
why killing infants, young children, and the severely retarded is
2 For interesting discussions of this issue, see Warren Quinn, Abortion: Identity
and Loss, Philosophy and Public Affairs, xiii, 1 (1984):24-54; and Lawrence C.
Becker, Human Being: The Boundaries of the Concept, Philosophy and Public
Affairs, iv, 4 (1975):334-359.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
186 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
wrong which are independent of her major principle that is sup-
posed to explain the wrongness of taking human life, but which will
not also make abortion immoral. This is no easy task. Appeals to
social utility will seem satisfactory only to those who resolve not to
think of the enormous difficulties with a utilitarian account of the
wrongness of killing and the significant social costs of preserving the
lives of the unproductive.3 A pro-choice strategy that extends the
definition of person to infants or even to young children seems just
as arbitrary as an anti-abortion strategy that extends the definition of
human being to fetuses. Again, we find symmetries in the two posi-
tions and we arrive at a standoff.
There are even further problems that reflect symmetries in the two
positions. In addition to counterexample problems, or the arbitrary
application problems that can be exchanged for them, the standard
anti-abortionist principle It is prima facie seriously wrong to kill a
human being, or one of its variants, can be objected to on the
grounds of ambiguity. If human being is taken to be a biological
category, then the anti-abortionist is left with the problem of ex-
plaining why a merely biological category should make a moral dif-
ference. Why, it is asked, is it any more reasonable to base a moral
conclusion on the number of chromosomes in ones cells than on the
color of ones skin?4 If human being, on the other hand, is taken to
be a moral category, then the claim that a fetus is a human being
cannot be taken to be a premise in the anti-abortion argument, for it
is precisely what needs to be established. Hence, either the anti-
abortionists main category is a morally irrelevant, merely biological
category, or it is of no use to the anti-abortionist in establishing
(noncircularly, of course) that abortion is wrong.
Although this problem with the anti-abortionist position is often
noticed, it is less often noticed that the pro-choice position suffers
from an analogous problem. The principle Only persons have the
right to life also suffers from an ambiguity. The term person is
typically defined in terms of psychological characteristics, although
there will certainly be disagreement concerning which characteristics
are most important. Supposing that this matter can be settled, the
pro-choicer is left with the problem of explaining why psychological
characteristics should make a moral difference. If the pro-choicer
should attempt to deal with this problem by claiming that an explana-
For example, see my Ethics and The Elderly: Some Problems, in Stuart
Spicker, Kathleen Woodward, and David Van Tassel, eds., Aging and the Elderly:
Humanistic Perspectives in Gerontology (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities,
1978), pp. 341-355.
4See Warren, op. cit., and Tooley, Abortion and Infanticide.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
WHY ABORTION IS IMMORAL 187
tion is not necessary, that in fact we do treat such a cluster of psycho-
logical properties as having moral significance, the sharp-witted
anti-abortionist should have a ready response. We do treat being
both living and human as having moral significance. If it is legitimate
for the pro-choicer to demand that the anti-abortionist provide an
explanation of the connection between the biological character of
being a human being and the wrongness of being killed (even though
people accept this connection), then it is legitimate for the anti-
abortionist to demand that the pro-choicer provide an explanation
of the connection between psychological criteria for being a person
and the wrongness of being killed (even though that connection is
accepted). 5
Feinberg has attempted to meet this objection (he calls psychologi-
cal personhood commonsense personhood):
The characteristics that confer commonsense personhood are not arbi-
trary bases for rights and duties, such as race, sex or species member-
ship; rather they are traits that make sense out of rights and duties and
without which those moral attributes would have no point or function. It
is because people are conscious; have a sense of their personal identities;
have plans, goals, and projects; experience emotions; are liable to pains,
anxieties, and frustrations; can reason and bargain, and so on-it is
because of these attributes that people have values and interests, desires
and expectations of their own, including a stake in their own futures,
and a personal well-being of a sort we cannot ascribe to unconscious or
nonrational beings. Because of their developed capacities they can as-
sume duties and responsibilities and can have and make claims on one
another. Only because of their sense of self, their life plans, their value
hierarchies, and their stakes in their own futures can they be ascribed
fundamental rights. There is nothing arbitrary about these linkages
(op. cit., p. 270).
The plausible aspects of this attempt should not be taken to obscure
its implausible features. There is a great deal to be said for the view
that being a psychological person under some description is a neces-
sary condition for having duties. One cannot have a duty unless one
is capable of behaving morally, and a beings capability of behaving
morally will require having a certain psychology. It is far from obvi-
ous, however, that having rights entails consciousness or rationality,
as Feinberg suggests. We speak of the rights of the severely retarded
or the severely mentally ill, yet some of these persons are not ra-
tional. We speak of the rights of the temporarily unconscious. The
New Jersey Supreme Court based their decision in the Quinlan case
This seems to be the fatal flaw in Warrens treatment of this issue.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
188 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
on Karen Ann Quinlans right to privacy, and she was known to be
permanently unconscious at that time. Hence, Feinbergs claim that
having rights entails being conscious is, on its face, obviously false.
Of course, it might not make sense to attribute rights to a being
that would never in its natural history have certain psychological
traits. This modest connection between psychological personhood
and moral personhood will create a place for Karen Ann Quinlan
and the temporarily unconscious. But then it makes a place for
fetuses also. Hence, it does not serve Feinbergs pro-choice pur-
poses. Accordingly, it seems that the pro-choicer will have as much
difficulty bridging the gap between psychological personhood and
personhood in the moral sense as the anti-abortionist has bridging
the gap between being a biological human being and being a human
being in the moral sense.
Furthermore, the pro-choicer cannot any more escape her prob-
lem by making person a purely moral category than the anti-abor-
tionist could escape by the analogous move. For if person is a moral
category, then the pro-choicer is left without the resources for es-
tablishing (noncircularly, of course) the claim that a fetus is not a
person, which is an essential premise in her argument. Again, we
have both a symmetry and a standoff between pro-choice and anti-
abortion views.
Passions in the abortion debate run high. There are both plausi-
bilities and difficulties with the standard positions. Accordingly, it is
hardly surprising that partisans of either side embrace with fervor
the moral generalizations that support the conclusions they preana-
lytically favor, and reject with disdain the moral generalizations of
their opponents as being subject to inescapable difficulties. It is easy
to believe that the counterexamples to ones own moral principles
are merely temporary difficulties that will dissolve in the wake of
further philosophical research, and that the counterexamples to the
principles of ones opponents are as straightforward as the contra-
diction between A and 0 propositions in traditional logic. This might
suggest to an impartial observer (if there are any) that the abortion
issue is unresolvable.
There is a way out of this apparent dialectical quandary. The moral
generalizations of both sides are not quite correct. The generaliza-
tions hold for the most part, for the usual cases. This suggests that
they are all accidental generalizations, that the moral claims made by
those on both sides of the dispute do not touch on the essence of the
matter.
This use of the distinction between essence and accident is not
meant to invoke obscure metaphysical categories. Rather, it is in-
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
WHY ABORTION IS IMMORAL 189
tended to reflect the rather atheoretical nature of the abortion dis-
cussion. If the generalization a partisan in the abortion dispute
adopts were derived from the reason why ending the life of a human
being is wrong, then there could not be exceptions to that general-
ization unless some special case obtains in which there are even more
powerful countervailing reasons. Such generalizations would not be
merely accidental generalizations; they would point to, or be based
upon, the essence of the wrongness of killing, what it is that makes
killing wrong. All this suggests that a necessary condition of resolving
the abortion controversy is a more theoretical account of the
wrongness of killing. After all, if we merely believe, but do not un-
derstand, why killing adult human beings such as ourselves is wrong,
how could we conceivably show that abortion is either immoral or
permissible?
II.
In order to develop such an account, we can start from the following
unproblematic assumption concerning our own case: it is wrong to
kill us. Why is it wrong? Some answers can be easily eliminated. It
might be said that what makes killing us wrong is that a killing bruta-
lizes the one who kills. But the brutalization consists of being inured
to the performance of an act that is hideously immoral; hence, the
brutalization does not explain the immorality. It might be said that
what makes killing us wrong is the great loss others would experience
due to our absence. Although such hubris is understandable, such an
explanation does not account for the wrongness of killing hermits, or
those whose lives are relatively independent and whose friends find it
easy to make new friends.
A more obvious answer is better. What primarily makes killing
wrong is neither its effect on the murderer nor its effect on the
victims friends and relatives, but its effect on the victim. The loss of
ones life is one of the greatest losses one can suffer. The loss of ones
life deprives one of all the experiences, activities, projects, and en-
joyments that would otherwise have constituted ones future. There-
fore, killing someone is wrong, primarily because the killing inflicts
(one of) the greatest possible losses on the victim. To describe this as
the loss of life can be misleading, however. The change in my biologi-
cal state does not by itself make killing me wrong. The effect of the
loss of my biological life is the loss to me of all those activities,
projects, experiences, and enjoyments which would otherwise have
constituted my future personal life. These activities, projects, experi-
ences, and enjoyments are either valuable for their own sakes or are
means to something else that is valuable for its own sake. Some parts
of my future are not valued by me now, but will come to be valued by
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
190 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
me as I grow older and as my values and capacities change. When I
am killed, I am deprived both of what I now value which would have
been part of my future personal life, but also what I would come to
value. Therefore, when I die, I am deprived of all of the value of my
future. Inflicting this loss on me is ultimately what makes killing me
wrong. This being the case, it would seem that what makes killing any
adult human being prima facie seriously wrong is the loss of his or
her future.6
How should this rudimentary theory of the wrongness of killing be
evaluated? It cannot be faulted for deriving an ought from an is,
for it does not. The analysis assumes that killing me (or you, reader) is
prima facie seriously wrong. The point of the analysis is to establish
which natural property ultimately explains the wrongness of the kill-
ing, given that it is wrong. A natural property will ultimately explain
the wrongness of killing, only if (1) the explanation fits with our
intuitions about the matter and (2) there is no other natural property
that provides the basis for a better explanation of the wrongness of
killing. This analysis rests on the intuition that what makes killing a
particular human or animal wrong is what it does to that particular
human or animal. What makes killing wrong is some natural effect or
other of the killing. Some would deny this. For instance, a divine-
command theorist in ethics would deny it. Surely this denial is, how-
ever, one of those features of divine-command theory which renders
it so implausible.
The claim that what makes killing wrong is the loss of the victims
future is, directly supported by two considerations. In the first place,
this theory explains why we regard killing as one of the worst of
crimes. Killing is especially wrong, because it deprives the victim of
more than perhaps any other crime. In the second place, people with
AIDS or cancer who know they are dying believe, of course, that
dying is a very bad thing for them. They believe that the loss of a
future to them that they would otherwise have experienced is what
makes their premature death a very bad thing for them. A better
theory of the wrongness of killing would require a different natural
property associated with killing which better fits with the attitudes of
the dying. What could it be?
The view that what makes killing wrong is the loss to the victim of
the value of the victims future gains additional support when some
of its implications are examined. In the first place, it is incompatible
h I have been most influenced on this matter byJonathan Glover, Causing Death
and Saving Lives (New York: Penguin, 1977), ch. 3; and Robert Young, What Is
So Wrong with Killing People? Philosophy, l iv, 210 (1979):515-528.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
WHY ABORTION IS IMMORAL 191
with the view that it is wrong to kill only beings who are biologically
human. It is possible that there exists a different species from an-
other planet whose members have a future like ours. Since having a
future like that is what makes killing someone wrong, this theory
entails that it would be wrong to kill members of such a species.
Hence, this theory is opposed to the claim that only life that is
biologically human has great moral worth, a claim which many anti-
abortionists have seemed to adopt. This opposition, which this
theory has in common with personhood theories, seems to be a merit
of the theory.
In the second place, the claim that the loss of ones future is the
wrong-making feature of ones being killed entails the possibility that
the futures of some actual nonhuman mammals on our own planet
are sufficiently like ours that it is seriously wrong to kill them also.
Whether some animals do have the same right to life as human beings
depends on adding to the account of the wrongness of killing some
additional account ofjust what it is about my future or the futures of
other adult human beings which makes it wrong to kill us. No such
additional account will be offered in this essay. Undoubtedly, the
provision of such an account would be a very difficult matter. Un-
doubtedly, any such account would be quite controversial. Hence, it
surely should not reflect badly on this sketch of an elementary theory
of the wrongness of killing that it is indeterminate with respect to
some very difficult issues regarding animal rights.
In the third place, the claim that the loss of ones future is the
wrong-making feature of ones being killed does not entail, as sanc-
tity of human life theories do, that active euthanasia is wrong. Per-
sons who are severely and incurably ill, who face a future of pain and
despair, and who wish to die will not have suffered a loss if they are
killed. It is, strictly speaking, the value of a humans future which
makes killing wrong in this theory. This being so, killing does not
necessarily wrong some persons who are sick and dying. Of course,
there may be other reasons for a prohibition of active euthanasia, but
that is another matter. Sanctity-of-human-life theories seem to hold
that active euthanasia is seriously wrong even in an individual case
where there seems to be good reason for it independently of public
policy considerations. This consequence is most implausible, and it is
a plus for the claim that the loss of a future of value is what makes
killing wrong that it does not share this consequence.
In the fourth place, the account of the wrongness of killing de-
fended in this essay does straightforwardly entail that it is prima facie
seriously wrong to kill children and infants, for we do presume that
they have futures of value. Since we do believe that it is wrong to kill
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Thu, 25 Sep 2014 13:21:31 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
192 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
defenseless little babies, it is important that a theory of …
Challenges to Human Equality
Author(s): Jeff McMahan
Source: The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 12, No. 1 (2008), pp. 81-104
Published by: Springer
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40345340
Accessed: 22-08-2016 20:32 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/40345340?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected]
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Ethics
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
JEFF MCMAHAN
CHALLENGES TO HUMAN EQUALITY
(Received 9 July 2006; accepted in revised form 9 July 2006)
ABSTRACT. According to liberal egalitarian morality, all human beings are one
anothers moral equals. Nonhuman animals, by contrast, are not considered to be our
moral equals. This essay considers two challenges to the liberal egalitarian view. One is the
separation problem, which is the challenge to identify a morally significant intrinsic
difference between a//human beings and all nonhuman animals. The other is the equality
problem, which is to explain how all human beings can be morally equal when there are
some human beings whose psychological capacities (and, in some cases, their psycho-
logical potentials as well) are no higher than those of certain nonhuman animals. The
focus throughout is on the ethics of killing but the arguments are of broader relevance.
The essay reaches a skeptical conclusion about our ability to meet these challenges.
KEY WORDS: animals, cognitive disability, equality, killing
1. The Separation Problem
In contemporary Western societies, common sense morality is liberal
egalitarian in character. With the possible exception of human beings
in their embryonic or fetal stages, all human beings are recognized -
in principle if not in practice - as one anothers moral equals. Each
human being matters equally; each has equal value and equal human
rights. One element of this liberal egalitarian view is the belief that all
wrongful killings of human beings are equally wrong, except, perhaps,
when there are relevant differences in the state of the agent, such as
the difference between a killing that the agent intends and one that
the agent merely foresees as a side effect of his action.1 In the book
1 The object of evaluation here is the causing of a human being to cease to exist,
not the manner in which the human being is killed. It may well be more seriously
wrong to kill a person in an agonizing manner than to kill the same person painlessly.
But this is because the former involves two distinct wrongs: causing the agony and
causing the death. The claim of equal wrongness applies to the causing of death
alone.
The Journal of Ethics (2008) 12:81-104
DOI 10.1007/sl0892-007-9020-9
© Springer 2007
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
82 CHALLENGES TO HUMAN EQUALITY
ably and generously reviewed by Rahul Kumar in the preceding
article, I discussed a more restricted view, which I called the equal
wrongness thesis.2 The equal wrongness thesis applies not to all
wrongful killings of human beings but only to wrongful killings of
persons - that is, individuals with psychological capacities beyond a
certain threshold of self-consciousness and minimal rationality.
According to the equal wrongness thesis, the extent to which it is
wrong to kill a person is unaffected by facts about the victim other
than those that may make him or her liable to be killed, or deserve to
be killed, if indeed it is possible for a person to deserve to be killed -
that is, facts other than those that may make the victim non-innocent
in the relevant sense. It is, according to the equal wrongness thesis, no
less seriously wrong to kill an old person than to kill a young person,
or to kill a person of melancholy disposition than to kill a person with
a happy temperament. The extent to which it is wrong to kill a person
is, in short, unaffected by the degree of loss or harm he would suffer
by being killed. Provided that he satisfies the criteria of personhood,
the wrongness of killing him is also unaffected by his nature or
capacities - for example, by whether he is virtuous or vicious, likable
or obnoxious, sensitive or insensitive, intelligent or unintelligent, and
so on. In the book, I neither endorsed nor challenged the equal
wrongness thesis, though my discussion of it was respectful and I
assumed it to be true for the sake of argument.
Most liberals insist that decisions not only about killing but even
about saving lives must not be based on quality of life consider-
ations, or quantity of life considerations. There is, however, some
disagreement about this, even among liberals, in cases other than
those involving wrongful killing. Some accept that when one can save
some but not all the people who will otherwise die, it can be
permissible, at least in some instances, to give priority to those who
would lose most by dying. And some accept that this can be
permissible as well in choices of whom to kill when circumstances
make it permissible to kill someone. Suppose, for example, that that a
runaway train is on a track leading to the station where another train
full of passengers has stopped. If nothing is done, the runaway train
will crash into the stationary train, killing hundreds of people. But
the train can be diverted onto one of two branching tracks before it
reaches the station. On one of these tracks there is a 20-year-old who
2 Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 233-248.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
JEFF MCMAHAN 83
cannot get off, while on the other there is a 90-year-old who cannot
get off. Most of us believe that it would be permissible to divert the
train onto one of the two tracks. Some liberals accept that it would be
permissible, or perhaps even required, to choose to kill the older
person on the ground that she would lose less by being killed, if there
were no weightier considerations that favored killing the younger
person instead. But many liberals believe that even in this kind of
case, equality requires that each of the two potential victims be given
an equal chance of surviving, so that, ideally, a randomizing device,
such as flipping a coin, should be used to determine onto which track
the train should be diverted. These people believe that a killing that
would be permissible if the choice of victim were made randomly
would be wrongful if the choice were made on the basis of a
comparison between the potential victims characteristics.
The equal wrongness thesis, which applies to wrongful killings of
persons, is deeply intuitive. Yet it is too weak to capture most
peoples intuitions, which extend the scope of equality beyond
persons to include all human beings, or at least all postnatal human
beings. Almost no one, however, believes that nonhuman animals are
our moral equals or have rights equal to ours. They are by definition
ineligible for human rights. And virtually everyone agrees that killing
an animal cannot be as seriously wrong as killing an innocent human
being, or a person. Not only are animals not our equals, but they are
not even equal among themselves; thus it is regarded as more
seriously wrong to kill a higher nonhuman animal, such as a
chimpanzee, than it is to kill a lower animal, such as a lizard.
When pressed to explain why animals lie outside the scope of
liberal egalitarian principles, such as the equal wrongness thesis, that
are thought to govern our treatment of other human beings, most
liberals respond initially by appealing to certain psychological
capacities that human beings possess but that animals lack. Human
beings, they point out, have capacities for self-consciousness,
rationality, autonomy, the use of language, action on the basis of
reasons, and so on. Some one or combination of these capacities is
what relevantly distinguishes human beings from animals and
provides the foundation for human equality. Yet according to the
common understanding of what it is to have a capacity, some human
beings lack all such capacities. Some, such as the severely demented
and the irreversibly comatose, lack them now but had them in the
past. Others, such as most fetuses and newborn infants, lack them
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
84 CHALLENGES TO HUMAN EQUALITY
now but have the potential to have them in the future.3 But some
human beings - namely, those that are congenitally and radically
cognitively impaired - have never had the capacities and also seem to
lack the potential to have them. And even among those human beings
who possess some of the capacities, there are some who do not
possess them all, while among those who possess them all, there are
some in whom the relevant capacities are more highly developed than
they are in others. How, then, can such capacities provide a basis for
human equality?
There are here two related but distinguishable problems for liberal
egalitarianism. One is to defend the common sense view that all human
beings are owed a form of consideration that is different from and
higher than that which is owed to other animals. The other is to show
how that form of consideration can be owed equally to all human
beings. I will call these the separation problem and the equality
problem, respectively. I believe that the separation problem cannot be
solved. If some individuals are owed a higher form of consideration
than is owed to any animal, that must be because they have certain
higher psychological capacities. An acceptable form of separation may
place most human beings above a relevant threshold of psychological
capacity, but it will leave some human beings below it and may place
some nonhuman animals above it. And if the threshold is defined by
psychological capacity, the equality problem will remain, though not
with respect to all human beings but with respect to all those
individuals above the relevant threshold.
Most philosophers believe that both these problems for liberal
egalitarianism can be solved. They believe that we can identify a basis
for distinguishing morally between human beings and nonhuman
animals that is not variable. They accept the relevance of psychological
capacities but claim that, while possession of higher psychological
capacities is sufficient for inclusion within the scope of liberal
egalitarian principles, such as the equal wrongness thesis, it is not
necessary. Human beings who lack the relevant capacities may
nevertheless be within the scope of the principles by virtue of having
a closely related characteristic. This type of response is defended by
Kumar, who contends that claims about the life-cycle of a particular
3 Liberal egalitarians who believe that abortion can be permissible may take the
fact that fetuses lack the relevant capacities as partial confirmation that it is these
capacities that distinguish most human beings from other animals. But if so, they
have a problem if they share the common opposition to infanticide (See Jeff
McMahan, Infanticide, Utilitas, forthcoming).
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
JEFF MCMAHAN 85
kind of living thing, or species, are just constitutive of what it is to be a
member of that species and that liberal egalitarian principles are
responsive, not just to the particular properties of an individual, but to
the characteristic life-cycle of the species to which that individual
belongs.4
There are two ways in which Kumars remarks can be interpreted.
In one passage he writes that
claims about species are not statistical generalizations. Rather, what they concern
is the essential nature of a living kind, revealing facts about the normal life-cycle
of that kind of living thing. The use of normal here is unashamedly normative.
... What respect for the value of a living thing requires will depend on the charac-
teristic life-cycle, or nature, of members of that [individuals] species.5
This passage suggests that in order to have the same moral status as a
normal human being, it is not necessary for an individual actually to
have a rational nature or to be internally directed toward the
development of a rational nature. Instead, these properties are
normatively characteristic of human beings - that is, all human beings
ought to have them even if there are some that do not. Because of this,
those human beings who will not have the normal or characteristic
human life-cycle, or who do not have the nature characteristic of
human beings, must nevertheless be accorded the same respect that
would be due to them if they did.
This view raises the question why facts about the nature of some
individuals could determine how other individuals that lack that
nature ought to be treated. Somehow membership in the same
biological kind is supposed to produce the requisite moral alchemy,
but it is opaque to me how this is supposed to work. I will not,
however, pursue this issue further here, as I have done so elsewhere.6
I will also not address certain other questions raised by this
interpretation, such as whether there is any basis for what is
normatively characteristic of a species other than what is statistically
characteristic of it, and, if not, why we should suppose that what is
statistically characteristic is invested with normative significance.
I will focus instead on a second interpretation of Kumars view.
According to this interpretation, what Kumar claims is that all human
beings are equal in their possession of the essential nature of human
4 Rahul Kumar, Permissible Killing and the Irrelevance of Being Human, The
Journal of Ethics, this issue (cited from two different paragraphs). Emphasis added.
5 Kumar, Permissible Killing and the Irrelevance of Being Human.
6 Jeff McMahan, Our Fellow Creatures, The Journal of Ethics 9 (2005),
pp. 355-359.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
86 CHALLENGES TO HUMAN EQUALITY
beings - the nature that defines their characteristic life-cycle and
includes having (or, perhaps, having had) a capacity for rational self-
governance, or being internally directed toward the development of such
a capacity.1 It is the possession of this essential nature that brings all
human beings within the scope of liberal egalitarian principles.
This view has much to recommend it. If successful, it brings all
human beings within the scope of liberal egalitarian principles, while
excluding all or most nonhuman animals. This does not mean,
however, that the view is committed to endorsing common sense
moralitys assignment of a vastly lower status to animals. It could
deny that most animals are our moral equals and yet concede that
perhaps some few of the higher animals are, while claiming that
others are worthy of significantly better treatment than they are
accorded by current practices. Admittedly, the view would disqualify
liberals who defend the permissibility of abortion from appealing for
support to claims about fetal status, such as the claim that fetuses are
not persons; yet these liberals could, as Kumar suggests, appeal to
arguments that focus instead on the fetuss lack of a right to the use of
the pregnant womans body as a means of life support. Unlike
arguments for abortion that appeal to fetal status, this sort of
argument has no tendency to support the permissibility of infanticide
- surely an advantage if we want to preserve deeply held intuitions.
Many of Kumars claims refer at least implicitly to biologically
immature human beings that lack the present capacity for rational
self-governance but nevertheless have the potential to develop that
capacity. He claims that respecting these individuals nature as
human beings involves not impeding and even facilitating the full
realization of their potential and thus their essential nature. In the
case of a human being that in a clear sense lacks even the potential for
rational self-governance, such as a fetus with defective genes that
direct the growth of the brain, he believes that respecting its nature
involves providing that potential if possible - for example, by
supplying it with properly functional genes for brain growth. For
given its nature as a human being, its lack of those genes is a
7 Kumar, Permissible Killing and the Irrelevance of Being Human. For a
similar view, see Robert P. George and Alfonso Gomez-Lobo, Statement of Pro-
fessor George (Joined by Dr. Gomez-Lobo), an appendix to Human Cloning and
Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry, a report by the Presidents Council on Bioethics,
available at http://www.bioethics.gov/topics/cloningjndex.html (accessed on 30
June 2006). And compare S. Matthew Liao, Virtually All Human Beings as
Rightholders, unpublished manuscript.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
JEFF MCMAHAN 87
misfortune, though the absence of those genes, and the associated
apparent lack of potential for rational self-governance, are not
misfortunes for a nonhuman animal.
There is a challenge here that I have not adequately addressed
either in my book or in a recent article in The Journal of Ethics in
which I advanced various arguments against views, such as Kumars,
that claim that the morality of our treatment of an individual ought
to be... guided by the moral norms that regulate how members of that
individuals species ought to be treated.8 The challenge derives from
the view that the reason why all human beings are included within the
scope of liberal egalitarian principles, such as the equal wrongness
thesis, is that they all have, as part of their essential nature or
constitution at all times at which they exist, either certain higher
psychological capacities, such as the capacity for rational self-
governance, or an inner directedness toward the possession or
development of those capacities. On this view, membership in the
human species is not morally significant only, or primarily, or
perhaps at all, because it involves a significant relation to other
human beings. It is significant because it is sufficient for the
possession of an intrinsically significant nature, whether or not that
nature is fully realized.9
Most mature human beings have a rational nature and most
immature human beings do seem to be inherently or internally
directed toward the development of the capacity for rationality.
Suppose we grant - what I believe to be plausible - that the actual
8 Kumar, Permissible Killing and the Irrelevance of Being Human. See
McMahan, Our Fellow Creatures.
9 What about human beings who once had higher psychological capacities but
have irreversibly lost them? There are two ways in which this view can attempt to
accommodate such individuals within the scope of liberal egalitarian principles. One
is to claim that even if the acquisition of a certain moral status requires the possession
of or potential for certain capacities, that status can nevertheless survive the loss of
those capacities and even the loss of the potential for those capacities. The other is to
claim that even if the areas of the brain that are the physical basis of an individuals
higher psychological capacities are destroyed, that individual remains genetically or
otherwise constituted to be directed toward the possession (though not the develop-
ment) of those capacities as long as he or she remains alive. I think the former of
these two claims is more plausible, in part because it provides a basis for the pos-
sibility of wronging the dead. Moral claims can not only survive an individuals loss
of capacities the possession of which was once necessary for the individual to be able
to exert those claims, but can even survive the death of the person who is the source
of the claims.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
88 CHALLENGES TO HUMAN EQUALITY
possession of a rational nature is sufficient to bring an individual
within the scope of liberal egalitarian principles.10 There remains the
familiar question about the potential for rationality as a basis for this
moral status: namely, why should an immature human beings
internal directedness toward the development of a rational nature
affect how we ought to treat that individual now? There is, of course,
a good answer to that question in cases in which how we treat the
individual now will affect her for better or worse later, when she
actually has a rational nature. But there are certain types of act the
effects of which are limited entirely to the present, including -
crucially - acts of killing. Why should the morality of an act of killing
be governed by the kind of respect that is appropriate for a nature
that the individual killed does not have now but may have later,
though only if it is not killed? Why should an act of killing not be
governed instead by due consideration for the nature of the
individual at the time of action (or of the death, if it occurs later)?
I believe, as I argued in The Ethics of Killing, that there are no
good answers to these questions. I will not rehearse those arguments
here but will instead raise what I think is a more difficult question.
What reason is there to suppose that all human beings are in fact
internally directed or programmed toward the development of a
rational nature? There are some human beings - those who are
congenitally and radically cognitively impaired (henceforth the
radically impaired) - who in at least one obvious sense lack the
potential for the development of a rational nature. While most
immature human beings (embryos, fetuses, newborn infants) will,
given a favorable environment, develop a capacity for rationality,
those immature human beings that are radically cognitively impaired
cannot develop this category, even with the most extensive forms of
assistance that we are currently able to provide.
For Kumars suggested strategy to succeed, there must be a clear
and morally significant sense in which the present nature of the
radically impaired is internally directed toward the development or
realization of a capacity for rationality, or rational self-governance.
Perhaps the most plausible claim for the defender of this strategy to
make is that the inherent tendency toward rationality is present in the
human genome, which the radically impaired share with the rest of
10 Perhaps there are exceptions in rare cases, such as extreme instances of psy-
chopathy, in which a human being has a developed capacity for instrumental
rationality but utterly lacks certain other capacities necessary for moral agency. I will
not explore this possibility here.
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
JEFF MCMAHAN 89
us. Their essential nature is thus inherent in their genes, but its
development or expression is impeded because the action of the genes
that direct the proper growth of the brain is somehow blocked. It may
be that their action is countermanded by some other malfunctioning
genes, or that something that is required for their activation is
missing, or that some of them are defective in some way.
If the genes for the proper growth of the brain are present but
something prevents their activation or blocks their action, there is a
clear sense in which the potential for a rational nature is present. But
it is less clear how long that potential persists. For the potential
consists in the ability of the genes to direct the growth of a normal
human brain, which is the physical basis of the capacity for
rationality. But if the action of the genes is impaired and the brain
grows abnormally, it appears that the potential for the growth of a
normally functioning brain has been lost. For the genes cannot direct
the growth of the brain once it already exists. If, even at this point,
those genes could direct the reconstruction or augmentation of the
defective brain in an identity-preserving way, then the potential, or
inner directedness, toward a rational nature would remain; but to the
best of my knowledge there is no reason to believe that the relevant
genes have that capacity. If that is right, then radically impaired
human beings whose condition results from the blocked functioning
of normal genes lose their internal directedness toward the possession
of a rational nature very early in life, when the development of their
brains passes a certain point.
What if the defective growth of the brain results not from the
blocked action of normal genes but from defects in the genes
themselves? Is it nonetheless the nature of these radically impaired
human beings to be rationally self-governing? It seems as if these
individuals were never internally directed toward the development of
the capacity for rationality but were always directed toward the
development of the cognitive capacities that they in fact have.
Consider an instance in which defective human genes direct a human
brain to grow in such a way that, when fully developed, its cognitive
powers are no higher than those of some lower animal. Certainly in
functional terms, and perhaps in structural terms as well, these genes
more closely resemble the corresponding genes of a lower animal than
they do their normally functioning human counterparts. Indeed,
because these defective human genes function to produce a brain with
powers of cognition similar to those of a lower animal, they are less
similar in functional terms to their properly functioning human
This content downloaded from 128.205.114.91 on Mon, 22 Aug 2016 20:32:58 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
90 CHALLENGES TO HUMAN EQUALITY
counterparts than are the corresponding genes in a higher animal,
which function to produce a brain with cognitive capacities closer to
those of a normal human brain. On what basis, then, can it be
claimed that it is the inherent nature of the individual whose genes
these are, but not the nature of a higher animal, to be internally
directed toward the realization of a capacity for rationality?
We have thus far considered that radical impairment could result
either from the suppression of the action of certain genes that carry
the code for the development of the human brain, or from defects in
the genes themselves. But there is another possibility. Some of the
relevant genes could be entirely absent. Whether such cases occur or
have occurred naturally is a question on which I have no information.
But even if they do not occur spontaneously in nature, they could
presumably be created by manipulating a pair of human gametes
prior to fertilization in a way that would ensure the deletion of certain
genes necessary for directing the normal growth of the brain. The
resulting radically impaired individual would certainly be a human
being by any reasonable criterion of species membership, whether
that criterion referred to genes, genealogy, capacity for interbreeding,
or whatever. There would then be a human being without any genetic
basis for the development of a rational nature. It would therefore be
hard to make sense of the idea that this human being would be
internally directed toward the full realization of its inherent nature as
a rational being.
Suppose there were a human fetus in this condition - that is, one
lacking some of the genes necessary for the development of a brain
with the capacity for rational thought. There is one sense in which
this individual might have the potential for a rational nature.
Suppose there were a therapy that could supply the missing gene or
genes and that if it were administered to the fetus, that fetus would
grow to produce a person with normal cognitive capacities rather
than being radically impaired. And suppose further that the
transformation would be identity-preserving, in that the person
would be the same individual that the radically impaired individual
would have been. The therapy, in other words, would determine
whether one and the same individual would have normal …
CATEGORIES
Economics
Nursing
Applied Sciences
Psychology
Science
Management
Computer Science
Human Resource Management
Accounting
Information Systems
English
Anatomy
Operations Management
Sociology
Literature
Education
Business & Finance
Marketing
Engineering
Statistics
Biology
Political Science
Reading
History
Financial markets
Philosophy
Mathematics
Law
Criminal
Architecture and Design
Government
Social Science
World history
Chemistry
Humanities
Business Finance
Writing
Programming
Telecommunications Engineering
Geography
Physics
Spanish
ach
e. Embedded Entrepreneurship
f. Three Social Entrepreneurship Models
g. Social-Founder Identity
h. Micros-enterprise Development
Outcomes
Subset 2. Indigenous Entrepreneurship Approaches (Outside of Canada)
a. Indigenous Australian Entrepreneurs Exami
Calculus
(people influence of
others) processes that you perceived occurs in this specific Institution Select one of the forms of stratification highlighted (focus on inter the intersectionalities
of these three) to reflect and analyze the potential ways these (
American history
Pharmacology
Ancient history
. Also
Numerical analysis
Environmental science
Electrical Engineering
Precalculus
Physiology
Civil Engineering
Electronic Engineering
ness Horizons
Algebra
Geology
Physical chemistry
nt
When considering both O
lassrooms
Civil
Probability
ions
Identify a specific consumer product that you or your family have used for quite some time. This might be a branded smartphone (if you have used several versions over the years)
or the court to consider in its deliberations. Locard’s exchange principle argues that during the commission of a crime
Chemical Engineering
Ecology
aragraphs (meaning 25 sentences or more). Your assignment may be more than 5 paragraphs but not less.
INSTRUCTIONS:
To access the FNU Online Library for journals and articles you can go the FNU library link here:
https://www.fnu.edu/library/
In order to
n that draws upon the theoretical reading to explain and contextualize the design choices. Be sure to directly quote or paraphrase the reading
ce to the vaccine. Your campaign must educate and inform the audience on the benefits but also create for safe and open dialogue. A key metric of your campaign will be the direct increase in numbers.
Key outcomes: The approach that you take must be clear
Mechanical Engineering
Organic chemistry
Geometry
nment
Topic
You will need to pick one topic for your project (5 pts)
Literature search
You will need to perform a literature search for your topic
Geophysics
you been involved with a company doing a redesign of business processes
Communication on Customer Relations. Discuss how two-way communication on social media channels impacts businesses both positively and negatively. Provide any personal examples from your experience
od pressure and hypertension via a community-wide intervention that targets the problem across the lifespan (i.e. includes all ages).
Develop a community-wide intervention to reduce elevated blood pressure and hypertension in the State of Alabama that in
in body of the report
Conclusions
References (8 References Minimum)
*** Words count = 2000 words.
*** In-Text Citations and References using Harvard style.
*** In Task section I’ve chose (Economic issues in overseas contracting)"
Electromagnetism
w or quality improvement; it was just all part of good nursing care. The goal for quality improvement is to monitor patient outcomes using statistics for comparison to standards of care for different diseases
e a 1 to 2 slide Microsoft PowerPoint presentation on the different models of case management. Include speaker notes... .....Describe three different models of case management.
visual representations of information. They can include numbers
SSAY
ame workbook for all 3 milestones. You do not need to download a new copy for Milestones 2 or 3. When you submit Milestone 3
pages):
Provide a description of an existing intervention in Canada
making the appropriate buying decisions in an ethical and professional manner.
Topic: Purchasing and Technology
You read about blockchain ledger technology. Now do some additional research out on the Internet and share your URL with the rest of the class
be aware of which features their competitors are opting to include so the product development teams can design similar or enhanced features to attract more of the market. The more unique
low (The Top Health Industry Trends to Watch in 2015) to assist you with this discussion.
https://youtu.be/fRym_jyuBc0
Next year the $2.8 trillion U.S. healthcare industry will finally begin to look and feel more like the rest of the business wo
evidence-based primary care curriculum. Throughout your nurse practitioner program
Vignette
Understanding Gender Fluidity
Providing Inclusive Quality Care
Affirming Clinical Encounters
Conclusion
References
Nurse Practitioner Knowledge
Mechanics
and word limit is unit as a guide only.
The assessment may be re-attempted on two further occasions (maximum three attempts in total). All assessments must be resubmitted 3 days within receiving your unsatisfactory grade. You must clearly indicate “Re-su
Trigonometry
Article writing
Other
5. June 29
After the components sending to the manufacturing house
1. In 1972 the Furman v. Georgia case resulted in a decision that would put action into motion. Furman was originally sentenced to death because of a murder he committed in Georgia but the court debated whether or not this was a violation of his 8th amend
One of the first conflicts that would need to be investigated would be whether the human service professional followed the responsibility to client ethical standard. While developing a relationship with client it is important to clarify that if danger or
Ethical behavior is a critical topic in the workplace because the impact of it can make or break a business
No matter which type of health care organization
With a direct sale
During the pandemic
Computers are being used to monitor the spread of outbreaks in different areas of the world and with this record
3. Furman v. Georgia is a U.S Supreme Court case that resolves around the Eighth Amendments ban on cruel and unsual punishment in death penalty cases. The Furman v. Georgia case was based on Furman being convicted of murder in Georgia. Furman was caught i
One major ethical conflict that may arise in my investigation is the Responsibility to Client in both Standard 3 and Standard 4 of the Ethical Standards for Human Service Professionals (2015). Making sure we do not disclose information without consent ev
4. Identify two examples of real world problems that you have observed in your personal
Summary & Evaluation: Reference & 188. Academic Search Ultimate
Ethics
We can mention at least one example of how the violation of ethical standards can be prevented. Many organizations promote ethical self-regulation by creating moral codes to help direct their business activities
*DDB is used for the first three years
For example
The inbound logistics for William Instrument refer to purchase components from various electronic firms. During the purchase process William need to consider the quality and price of the components. In this case
4. A U.S. Supreme Court case known as Furman v. Georgia (1972) is a landmark case that involved Eighth Amendment’s ban of unusual and cruel punishment in death penalty cases (Furman v. Georgia (1972)
With covid coming into place
In my opinion
with
Not necessarily all home buyers are the same! When you choose to work with we buy ugly houses Baltimore & nationwide USA
The ability to view ourselves from an unbiased perspective allows us to critically assess our personal strengths and weaknesses. This is an important step in the process of finding the right resources for our personal learning style. Ego and pride can be
· By Day 1 of this week
While you must form your answers to the questions below from our assigned reading material
CliftonLarsonAllen LLP (2013)
5 The family dynamic is awkward at first since the most outgoing and straight forward person in the family in Linda
Urien
The most important benefit of my statistical analysis would be the accuracy with which I interpret the data. The greatest obstacle
From a similar but larger point of view
4 In order to get the entire family to come back for another session I would suggest coming in on a day the restaurant is not open
When seeking to identify a patient’s health condition
After viewing the you tube videos on prayer
Your paper must be at least two pages in length (not counting the title and reference pages)
The word assimilate is negative to me. I believe everyone should learn about a country that they are going to live in. It doesnt mean that they have to believe that everything in America is better than where they came from. It means that they care enough
Data collection
Single Subject Chris is a social worker in a geriatric case management program located in a midsize Northeastern town. She has an MSW and is part of a team of case managers that likes to continuously improve on its practice. The team is currently using an
I would start off with Linda on repeating her options for the child and going over what she is feeling with each option. I would want to find out what she is afraid of. I would avoid asking her any “why” questions because I want her to be in the here an
Summarize the advantages and disadvantages of using an Internet site as means of collecting data for psychological research (Comp 2.1) 25.0\% Summarization of the advantages and disadvantages of using an Internet site as means of collecting data for psych
Identify the type of research used in a chosen study
Compose a 1
Optics
effect relationship becomes more difficult—as the researcher cannot enact total control of another person even in an experimental environment. Social workers serve clients in highly complex real-world environments. Clients often implement recommended inte
I think knowing more about you will allow you to be able to choose the right resources
Be 4 pages in length
soft MB-920 dumps review and documentation and high-quality listing pdf MB-920 braindumps also recommended and approved by Microsoft experts. The practical test
g
One thing you will need to do in college is learn how to find and use references. References support your ideas. College-level work must be supported by research. You are expected to do that for this paper. You will research
Elaborate on any potential confounds or ethical concerns while participating in the psychological study 20.0\% Elaboration on any potential confounds or ethical concerns while participating in the psychological study is missing. Elaboration on any potenti
3 The first thing I would do in the family’s first session is develop a genogram of the family to get an idea of all the individuals who play a major role in Linda’s life. After establishing where each member is in relation to the family
A Health in All Policies approach
Note: The requirements outlined below correspond to the grading criteria in the scoring guide. At a minimum
Chen
Read Connecting Communities and Complexity: A Case Study in Creating the Conditions for Transformational Change
Read Reflections on Cultural Humility
Read A Basic Guide to ABCD Community Organizing
Use the bolded black section and sub-section titles below to organize your paper. For each section
Losinski forwarded the article on a priority basis to Mary Scott
Losinksi wanted details on use of the ED at CGH. He asked the administrative resident