DP5 - English
371
HUMAN EXTINCTION AND THE VALUE OF OUR EFFORTS
BROOKE ALAN TRISEL
THE PHILOSOPHICAL FORUM
Volume XXXV, No. 3, Fall 2004
Discussions about nuclear weapons, the depletion of the ozone layer, and the
possibility that a massive asteroid could crash into Earth, prompt us to reflect
on our own individual mortality and on human extinction. And when we think
about the end of humanity, it raises questions about whether our efforts have
value because, if human extinction does occur, the things that we have created
will decay and eventually vanish. Some claim that our efforts are pointless if
humanity will cease to exist. This claim will be examined and disputed in this
essay.
In recent years, there has been extensive debate regarding the question of
whether we have obligations to future generations, such as an obligation to pre-
serve the environment. To a far lesser extent, there has also been discussion about
the more basic question of whether it matters how long humanity will persist.
The related question of whether our efforts have value if humanity will end has
received even less attention.
The human species could become extinct abruptly, with all of us dying at once
or within a short time of each other. Extinction could also occur gradually. For
example, if people would immediately stop having children, then we would live
out our lives in a world without future generations. Humanity would become
extinct over a period of 110 to 120 years—the maximum life span of someone
currently alive.
If we knew that humanity would become extinct within the next few months,
then we would be justified in feeling distressed about this because it would cut
short our expected life span, thereby depriving us of many potential experiences.
However, should we feel anguish about the possibility that humankind will
become extinct long after we and our loved ones have died?
I would like to thank an anonymous referee for valuable comments and suggestions.
It is understandable why we want those that we love, including our children and
friends, to continue living after we have died. Because we love them, relate to them
as one existent individual to another, and empathize with their feelings and aspira-
tions, we desire for them to live on so that they can realize their goals and experience
fulfilling lives. But why should it matter whether remote future generations—
faceless, abstract persons who only potentially exist and whom we will never
know—will be born after we have died and will persist for as long as possible?
Ernest Partridge contends that people have a “basic need” to care for the future
beyond their own lifetimes, a need that he refers to as “self transcendence.”1 He
writes:
By claiming that there is a basic human need for “self transcendence,” I am proposing that, as a
result of the psychodevelopmental sources of the self and the fundamental dynamics of social expe-
rience, well-functioning human beings identify with, and seek to further, the well-being, preser-
vation, and endurance of communities, locations, causes, artifacts, institutions, ideals, and so on,
that are outside themselves and that they hope will flourish beyond their own lifetimes.2
In attempting to support his claim, Partridge argues that there is a “desire to
extend the term of one’s influence and significance well beyond the term of one’s
lifetime—a desire evident in arrangements for posthumous publications, in
bequests and wills, in perpetual trusts (such as the Nobel Prize), and so forth.”3
Partridge concludes by asserting:
To be sure, posterity does not actually exist now. Even so, in a strangely abstract and metaphori-
cal sense, posterity may extend profound favors for the living. For posterity exists as an idea, a
potentiality, and a valid object of transpersonal devotion, concern, purpose, and commitment.
Without this idea and potentiality, our lives would be confined, empty, bleak, pointless, and morally
impoverished.4
Allen Tough makes a similar argument to Partridge when he states: “If our
future is highly negative [referring to the end of humanity], then most other values
and goals will lose their point.”5
In this essay, an attempt will be made to demonstrate that the claim that our
lives would be empty and pointless without future generations is greatly exag-
BROOKE ALAN TRISEL
372
1 Partridge uses the term “self transcendence” to mean extending one’s influence beyond one’s life-
time. Others use this word in a broader sense to mean extending one’s influence or help to other
people, regardless of whether they are future persons and so, to avoid confusion, this word will not
be used.
2 Ernest Partridge, “Why Care About the Future?” in Responsibilities to Future Generations:
Environmental Ethics, ed. Ernest Partridge (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1981), 204.
3 Ibid., 209.
4 Ibid., 217–218.
5 Allen Tough, Crucial Questions About the Future (New York: UP of America, 1991), 12.
gerated. Second, it will be argued that, if we adopt a reasonable standard for
judging whether our efforts are “significant,” it then will not matter whether
humanity will persist for an extended time.
BACKGROUND ON THE DEBATE
Many people have expressed a longing for humanity to persist for as long as
possible. Wilhelm Ostwald, for example, argues that the continuation of a species
is a way of mitigating the death of an individual member of that species. In the
context of discussing the propagation of biological organisms, he writes: “Death
has here lost much of his power; many individuals may perish, but the organism
as such remains alive. Only when the very last of all the offspring perishes may
death be regarded as the victor.”6 Avner de-Shalit expresses a similar view insofar
as he argues that the idea of future generations helps people overcome the fear
of death. He writes: “We can, to a certain extent, and should immortalize the
creative part of us. True, this is not a total victory over the fear [of death], nor is
it a full answer. Nevertheless, if we follow this course of action, it will provide
us with a certain victory.”7
In writing about “traces,” as they are now called, Ostwald indicates: “Every
man leaves after his death certain things in the world changed by his influence.
He may have built a house, or gained a fortune, or written a book, or begotten
children.”8 He goes on to argue: “There is a very general desire in mankind to
leave such impressions” and “we are not fully satisfied with the mere existence
of such objective souvenirs [referring to the pyramids], but want other people to
see them and realize their meaning.”9
The principal argument advanced by those who believe that it matters how long
humanity will persist is as follows: People desire to leave an enduring trace of
their existence and would not be satisfied in just leaving a physical trace. People
want their trace (e.g., piece of artwork) to be appreciated by other people—not
just to sit on a desolate planet for countless years. Leaving an appreciable, endur-
ing trace is dependent on the existence of future generations. Therefore, it matters,
they conclude, how long humanity will continue to exist.
HUMAN EXTINCTION AND THE VALUE OF OUR EFFORTS
373
6 Wilhelm Ostwald, Individuality and Immortality (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1906), 14.
A scholar from various disciplines is invited each year to deliver the “Ingersoll Lecture on the
Immortality of Man.” At the time of his lecture, which was published in the book, Ostwald was a
Professor of Physical Chemistry at the University of Leipzig and a Temporary Professor at Harvard
University, where he delivered the lecture.
7 Avner de-Shalit, Why Posterity Matters: Environmental Policies and Future Generations (London:
Routledge, 1995), 38.
8 Ostwald, op. cit., 53.
9 Ibid., 54–55.
James Lenman convincingly argues that, from an impersonal standpoint, it does
not matter whether humanity will become extinct sooner rather than later.10
However, he does believe that this matters from a “generation-centered” per-
spective for reasons similar to those advanced by Partridge and de-Shalit.
It is true, as Partridge maintains, that some people do adopt goals that extend
beyond the end of their lives. For example, in response to a question regarding
the goal of a writer, William Faulkner remarks:
It’s—I think that a writer wants to make something that he knows that a hundred or two hundred
or five hundred, a thousand years later will make people feel what they feel when they read Homer,
or read Dickens or Balzac, Tolstoy . . . he knows he has a short span of life, that the day will come
when he must pass through the wall of oblivion, and he wants to leave a scratch on that wall—
Kilroy was here—that somebody a hundred, a thousand years later will see.11
Granted, if one’s goal is to influence people for thousands of years through
one’s writings, then this goal could not be accomplished without the continued
existence of humanity. However, the goal of leaving an enduring, appreciable
trace is not important, as will be shown in a later section. Furthermore, adopting
such a grandiose goal is unrealistic, especially considering the vast quantity of
writings that are being produced and amassed by humanity. Although future
persons may have more sophisticated technology than we do to sift through these
writings, they (like us) will be limited in how much they can read. Therefore, it
will be difficult for a contemporary writer to achieve the goal of influencing future
persons for thousands of years.
Partridge argues that it should matter to us how long humanity will persist, but
clearly this does not matter to everyone. For example, in response to the com-
ments of an earlier presenter at a symposium, who had equated the 4.5 billion
years of earth’s history to once around the world in a plane, the economist Lester
Thurow responded: “Do I care what happens a thousand years from now? Do I
care when man gets off the airplane? And I think I basically came to the conclu-
sion that I don’t care whether man is on the airplane for another eight feet, or if
man is on the airplane another three times around the earth.”12
Thurow does not expound on why he does not care how long humanity will
persist. However, for some people, a pessimistic outlook on life explains why
they do not embrace the goal of achieving human immortality. According to the
BROOKE ALAN TRISEL
374
10 James Lenman, “On Becoming Extinct,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (2002), 253–69.
11 William Faulkner, Faulkner in the University: Class Conferences at the University of Virginia,
1957–1958, ed. Frederick L. Gwynn & Joseph L. Blotner (New York: Vintage Books, 1959), 61.
12 Lester Thurow, “Zero Economic Growth and the Distribution of Income,” The Economic Growth
Controversy, eds. Andrew Weintraub, Eli Schwartz, & J. Richard Aronson (White Plains: Inter-
national Arts and Sciences Press, Inc., 1973), 141–2.
noted pessimist Schopenhauer: “You can also look upon our life as an episode
unprofitably disturbing the blessed calm of nothingness.”13 To those who believe
that nonexistence is preferable to existence or that evil outweighs the good in the
world, the goal that humanity will persist for billions of years undoubtedly seems
irrational and perhaps even ridiculous. From their perspective, it is unlikely that
this goal could be achieved considering the destructive behavior of humankind
and, even if it could be achieved, we would never know it because we would no
longer be alive then. Furthermore, achieving this goal would only prolong human
suffering and misery and postpone the inevitable extinction of humankind. For
example, Schopenhauer writes:
If the act of procreation were neither the outcome of a desire nor accompanied by feelings of plea-
sure, but a matter to be decided on the basis of purely rational considerations, is it likely the human
race would still exist? Would each of us not rather have felt so much pity for the coming genera-
tion as to prefer to spare it the burden of existence, or at least not wish to take it upon himself to
impose that burden upon it in cold blood?14
If one is miserable with one’s life, then this person may wish that he or she had
never been born, may assume that others also wish they had never been born, and
thus may see themselves as doing future persons a favor by sparing them the
“burden of existence.” However, the assumption that everyone desires not to have
been born must be false, because, if it were true, then there would be many more
suicides than there are and people would not seek, as they do, to live as long as
possible—some even wanting to live forever.
As extreme pessimism is uncommon, there must be other reasons explaining
why it does not matter to some people, such as Thurow, whether humanity will
endure for a long time. These reasons will become evident in the next section,
where it will be demonstrated that the claim that our efforts would be pointless
without future generations is an exaggeration.
LIFE WITHOUT FUTURE GENERATIONS
One can lead a meaningful life without personal immortality or a superior
being, as many have argued.15 If living forever, as an individual, is unnecessary
for one’s life to be meaningful, then this immediately raises doubt about whether
HUMAN EXTINCTION AND THE VALUE OF OUR EFFORTS
375
13 Arthur Schopenhauer, “On the Suffering of the World,” Essays and Aphorisms, trans. R.J.
Hollingdale (London: Penguin Books, 1970), 47.
14 Ibid., 47–48.
15 See, for example, Kurt Baier, “The Meaning of Life,” The Meaning of Life, ed. E. D. Klemke (New
York: Oxford UP, 2000), 101–132. Inaugural Lecture delivered at Canberra University College,
1957.
it is necessary for humanity to live forever, or for a long time, for one’s life to
be meaningful, as some claim. It will be useful, however, to examine their argu-
ments in more detail.
Would our lives be “pointless” without future generations as Partridge claims?
“Pointless” is a vague word and Partridge does not elaborate on what he means
in using this word. Therefore, before addressing the question, it is important to
attain a clear understanding of the meanings of this word. “Pointless” can mean
the same as “purposeless,” which signifies the absence of a goal or purpose.
Clearly, living without the prospect of future generations is not pointless, in this
sense of the word, because people alive today can have and pursue goals regard-
less of whether there will be future generations.
“Pointless” can also mean that one has a goal, but that it no longer makes sense
to continue striving to achieve this goal because conditions have changed that
have made the goal irrelevant or unachievable. In this sense of the word, “point-
less” has a meaning very similar to “futile.” Declaring that an action or activity
will be futile means that it will be impossible or highly improbable that the action,
no matter how often it will be repeated, will bring about one’s envisioned goal.
Therefore, whether or not an effort is considered futile or pointless will depend,
in large part, on the nature of one’s goals.16
A few of the goals that some people have would be pointless without future
generations. For example, if one’s goal is to write a book that will be read by and
influence others for thousands of years, then, if it becomes known that humankind
will perish within six months, this individual would consider the writing of this
book pointless because the envisioned goal has become unachievable. Although
the goal would be pointless, it is unrealistic to adopt such a goal in the first place.
Our lives, as a whole, would be pointless without future generations only if all
of our efforts were devoted to achieving goals directed at future persons and this
is not true. Most of peoples’ goals can be accomplished within their lifetimes. If
all of our goals extended well beyond our lifetimes, then we would not fully
realize any of our goals until long after we have died. But people do accomplish
many of their goals: they graduate from college, they get married, they pursue
various careers, they write books, they travel, and so on—all without future
generations.
Animals preceded human life by millions of years and may continue to exist
for millions of years after humanity has become extinct. Some people have goals
directed at assuring that other forms of life, especially animals, will survive and
flourish, regardless of how long humanity will persist. Arne Naess argues that one
BROOKE ALAN TRISEL
376
16 For a more detailed analysis and discussion of the concept of futility, see Brooke Alan Trisel,
“Futility and the Meaning of Life Debate,” Sorites 14 (October 2002), 70–84.
http://www.sorites.org/Issue_14/trisel.htm
http://www.sorites.org/Issue_14/trisel.htm
of the values underlying the “deep ecology” movement is the principle of “bios-
pherical egalitarianism.” He writes:
The ecological field-worker acquires a deep-seated respect, or even veneration, for ways and forms
of life. He reaches an understanding from within, a kind of understanding that others reserve for
fellow men and for a narrow section of ways and forms of life. To the ecological field-worker, the
equal right to live and blossom is an intuitively clear and obvious value axiom.17
Paul Taylor outlines a “biocentric outlook” on nature.18 One of the four com-
ponents of this outlook is that human beings are members of Earth’s community
of life and hold that membership on the same terms as nonhuman members.
He expresses the desire to maintain the “integrity of the biosphere” for the good
of human and nonhuman members of the community of life. Taylor argues
that if human extinction should occur that “not only would the Earth’s commu-
nity of life continue to exist, but in all probability, its well-being would be
enhanced.”19
As Taylor’s goal extends beyond humanity to include animals and plants, pur-
suing this goal would not be pointless even if humanity will become extinct
because achieving this goal does not depend on the continued existence of human-
ity. In fact, as he argues, the continued existence of humanity actually makes it
more difficult to achieve the goal that animals will survive. Those who argue that
our lives would be pointless without future generations falsely assume that every-
one’s goals revolve around and are limited to human beings.
For the preceding reasons, it is an overstatement to claim that our efforts would
be pointless without future generations. If one’s goals do not extend beyond one’s
lifetime or are directed at nonhuman life, then it may be possible to achieve these
goals even if there will be no future generations.
Wanting to influence humanity forever would be pointless without future gen-
erations, but this should not concern us. Trying to run a marathon in five minutes,
and attempting to jump to the moon from Earth, are also pointless. These latter
two activities are pointless because these goals exceed human capabilities and are
unachievable. No matter how much effort is expended, one could never achieve
these goals. Wanting to leave an everlasting trace of ourselves also exceeds human
capabilities and is unachievable. If a person would try to jump to the moon or to
leave a trace that will last forever, then this person’s efforts related to these goals
HUMAN EXTINCTION AND THE VALUE OF OUR EFFORTS
377
17 Arne Naess, “The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement: A Summary,” Inquiry
16 (1973), 95–100.
18 Paul W. Taylor, “The Ethics of Respect for Nature,” Environmental Philosophy: From Animal
Rights to Radical Ecology, ed. Michael E. Zimmerman (Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
Inc. 1998), 71–86.
19 Ibid., 76.
will be futile. However, they would not be justified in feeling distressed about
this because they chose unrealistic goals, which primarily is why their efforts
toward achieving these goals would be futile.
It does not concern us that we cannot jump to the moon because we under-
stand that human beings have limits and that a jump of this magnitude far exceeds
our capabilities. We accept this limitation and do not fret about it, yet some people
resist accepting the limitation that they cannot leave an everlasting, appreciable
trace of themselves. By accepting this limitation and adopting realistic goals, it
will help assure that our efforts will not be pointless.
In addition to claiming that our lives would be pointless without future gener-
ations, Partridge also claims that our lives would be “empty” and “bleak” without
future generations because purportedly we could not satisfy the desire or goal to
leave an enduring trace of ourselves without them. This, however, falsely assumes
that having and achieving goals are the only experiences that make living worth-
while. Even more incorrect, it assumes that being able to achieve one kind of
goal, namely a goal that extends beyond one’s life and is directed at future
persons, is the only experience that makes life worth living.
Having and achieving goals can give us a sense of purpose, direction, and sat-
isfaction, but these are not the only experiences that make living worthwhile.
There are other commendable aspects of life, such as aesthetic appreciation and
being with family and friends, which may have little or nothing to do with goal-
directed activity. Therefore, it is untrue that our lives would be empty and bleak
without future generations.
In contrast to those who have goals that extend beyond their lives, people who
are not achievement-oriented, or are achievement-oriented but who set realistic
goals, may not care whether humanity will persist for a long time. Having goals
that extend beyond the end of their lives may be common among those who
produce creative works such as writers and artists, but are these goals that preva-
lent among ordinary people, as those who long for future generations suggest? It
is doubtful that individuals whose profession involves providing a service, such
as delivering the mail, or caring for a patient in the hospital, really care whether
they will leave a trace of their existence that will last thousands of years. Their
goals and interests may not extend much, if any, beyond the point at which they,
and those that they love, will cease living. Consequently, it may not matter to
them whether humanity will persist for a long time.
What if there are objective values independent of human subjective evaluation,
as some believe? If there are objective values, then a discrepancy could occur
between what we think is important and what is important according to this objec-
tive standard. We could conclude that it does not matter how long humanity will
continue to exist when it really does matter or that it does matter when it really
does not.
BROOKE ALAN TRISEL
378
Let us suppose that there is a god who has given us objective standards declar-
ing what is right and wrong and what is significant and insignificant and that we
have somehow discovered the following standard:
a. The things that human beings create are significant regardless of how
long they will last.
If there were such an objective standard, then our creations would be significant
regardless of what we think of them and regardless of whether future persons val-
idate that they are significant. Even if humanity would be wiped out next month,
creating things would not be pointless since the significance of these creations
does not depend on how long they will last.
If there are no objective standards, as I believe, then the question becomes what
criteria should be selected to decide what is and what is not significant. With the
standard considered above, we do not know why this god considers our creations
significant, but we do know that the length of time that our creations will last is
not one of the criteria used by this god to judge significance.
The standards that we adopt are based upon our desires and goals. Reflecting
their goals, some people adopt the following standard to judge significance:
b. My creations are significant only if they will be appreciated by others
for a long time.
If people adopt this standard, then whether or not their creations are considered
significant will depend on how long these creations will be appreciated which, in
turn, will depend on how long humanity will last. This raises the fundamental
question of whether long-lastingness should be part of a standard for judging sig-
nificance. As will be argued in greater detail later, including long-lastingness as
one of the criteria for judging the significance of our efforts is unreasonable and
unwise.
THE END OF THE UNIVERSE
It is important to distinguish the end of humanity from the end of the universe
since the universe may continue to exist and be habitable to life for a long time
after humanity becomes extinct. At a time at which a few scientists were pre-
dicting that the universe would ultimately end in “heat death”—a prediction based
upon generalizing (inappropriately, some would argue) the Second Law of
Thermodynamics to the whole universe—Bertrand Russell wrote the following
famous words:
HUMAN EXTINCTION AND THE VALUE OF OUR EFFORTS
379
all the labors of the ages, all the devotion, all the inspiration, all the noonday brightness of human
genius, are destined to extinction in the vast death of the solar system, and that the whole temple
of man’s achievement must inevitably be buried beneath the debris of a universe in ruins—all these
things, if not quite beyond dispute, are yet so nearly certain that no philosophy which rejects them
can hope to stand.20
Despite these gloomy words, Russell did not conclude that living is pointless or
bleak if humanity or the universe will eventually end. However, some people do
reach this conclusion.
John Barrow and Frank Tipler, in outlining the much-debated “Anthropic Cos-
mological Principle,” and in reaction to Russell’s comments quoted above, write:
Though our species is doomed, our civilization and indeed the values we care about may not be.
We emphasized . . . that from the behavioral point of view intelligent machines can be regarded as
people. These machines may be our ultimate heirs, our ultimate descendants, because under certain
circumstances they could survive forever the extreme conditions near the Final State. Our
civilization may be continued indefinitely by them, and the values of humankind may thus be
transmitted to an arbitrarily distant futurity.21
We realize that we will die long before the universe will end. Nevertheless,
some people are distressed with the thought that the universe may end one way
or another. In fact, they may feel more distress thinking about the end of the uni-
verse than about the extinction of humankind. What is the explanation for this?
It will be hypothesized that the level of distress that one feels about the possi-
bility that the universe will end varies with the nature of one’s goals (e.g., whether
one wants to leave an everlasting trace), one’s theory of value, and one’s
religious beliefs.
Before exploring these relations, it will be useful to clarify what the “end” of
the universe means, as the “end” could be thought of in many different ways. The
end of the universe could be thought of as the last event. It might also be thought
of as a point at which the universe vanishes into nothingness, if one assumed this
was possible. For the purposes of this discussion, the end of the universe will be
defined as a point at which the universe has become irreversibly inhospitable to
life and has irreversibly lost all traces of its prior states.
As discussed in the previous section, some people have goals that are not
dependent on the continued existence of humanity. However, achieving these
BROOKE ALAN TRISEL
380
20 Bertrand Russell, “A Free Man’s Worship,” Why I Am Not a Christian, and Other Essays on
Religion and Related Subjects, ed. Paul Edwards (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1957), 107.
Originally published in The Independent Review, 1903.
21 John D. Barrow & Frank J. Tipler, The Anthropic Cosmological Principle (Oxford: Oxford
UP, 1986), 615.
goals may be dependent on the universe having certain characteristics, such as
being habitable to life. For example, it would not be possible for animals or
ecosystems to survive after the extinction of humankind if the universe ends
shortly after humanity does. If people think of animals as having only instru-
mental value to human beings, then this scenario will not concern them. However,
if they believe that certain aspects of nature, such as animals, are intrinsically
valuable,22 then the destruction of the universe would signify the loss of these
values.
Some people want to leave an enduring, appreciable trace and do not believe
that there is a god who will outlast the universe or that there are objective …
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
ON BECOMING EXTINCT 253
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (2002) 253–269 0279 – 0750/00/0100 – 0000
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. Published by
Blackwell Publishers, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and
350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
253
ON BECOMING
EXTINCT
JAMES LENMAN
Abstract: From an impersonal, timeless perspective it is hard to identify good
reasons why it should matter that human extinction comes later rather than
sooner, particularly if we accept that it does not matter how many human
beings there are. We cannot appeal to the natural narrative shape of human
history for there is no such thing. We have more local and particular concerns
to which we can better appeal but only if an impersonal, timeless perspective
is abandoned: only from a generation-centred perspective do such concerns
help to make sense of our concern for the timing of our own extinction.
1.
Everybody dies. Perhaps, though there are grounds for doubt1, this is a
bad thing. There are fewer grounds for doubting that, given that we all
die, it is a bad thing when we die prematurely, before we have lived out
the natural span of a human life. A long life, for one thing, is something
that we all tend to want. Not only do we want this but we want many
other things that presuppose it: to bring certain projects to completion,
to support our children – if we have them – until they grow to independ-
ence, and so on. Of course we may also want things that would presup-
pose a two or three hundred year life-span but we want these latter things
more or less idly. The tragedy of not living to be twenty-five or twelve
is of a different order from the tragedy of not living to be five hundred:
the difference is that between wanting to be happy human beings and
wanting to be something else.
When we think of human wellbeing – as I suspect we should – in terms
of the constitutive goods of human life we see clearly what is tragic in an
early death. These constitutive goods may include the pleasures of play-
ing with our grandchildren and witnessing their early development, of
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM253
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
254 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY
relaxation in retirement after the longer-term analogue to a hard day’s
work and other good things that belong properly to the later years of a
life no less than the goods and pleasures that may attach more naturally
to childhood and youth.2 Up to a point then, and other things being
equal, we may sensibly think that, while human lives must end, it is better
to prolong them, when possible, to their full span. Only up to a point
perhaps, because sometimes the quality of someone’s life may become so
irreversibly bad that it becomes at least unclear whether it would be a
good thing to prolong it further. And only other things being equal,
because most of us believe there may be things worth dying for. But so
qualified, there seems little to argue with in the thought that it is better if
our lives are longer rather than shorter.
At work here perhaps is some notion of the narrative shape of a full
human life. Such a life has a certain narrative structure: a beginning,
comprising childhood and youth, where we spend much of our energy in
learning and developing in ways that will stand us in good stead for what
comes afterwards; then there is adult life where we may make some con-
tribution to society through work or assemble a family and raise children;
and then there is old age when (if we are fortunate) we may relax in the
fruition of all this. To have one’s life truncated is to miss out on parts of
this progress in ways it makes great sense for us not to welcome.
2.
It is not only individuals who die. Species also die or die out. Today there
are no longer any sabre-tooth tigers or Irish elk and, one day, certainly,
there will be no human beings. Perhaps that is a bad thing but, if so, it
is a bad thing we had better learn to live with. The Second Law of
Thermodynamics will get us in the end in the fantastically unlikely event
that nothing else does first. We might perhaps argue about whether and
how much this inevitability should distress us but that it not my present
purpose. Rather I want to ask whether, given that any given species will
at some time disappear, it is better that it disappear later rather than
sooner. More particularly, given that it is inevitable that our own species
will only endure for a finite time, does it matter how soon that end
comes?
We are naturally disposed to think it would be a bad thing were our
extinction imminent. In popular movies like Armageddon, everyone is
very unhappy with this prospect for an obvious and extremely under-
standable reason – they are all going to die very soon. The trouble is that
if we take a timeless and impersonal perspective, this might seem to be no
big deal. For, on such a perspective, future people matter no less than do
present people. And this fate is waiting for some generation or other.
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM254
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
ON BECOMING EXTINCT 255
Of course it needn’t be quite this fate. Rather than getting wiped
out in a nasty catastrophe, we might just fade away. Something in the
water might make us all less fertile with the result that human population
dwindles away, over a few generations, to nothing. Even this would not
be painless: it would mean loneliness and hardship in the last years as
the final generation grew old without the emotional and material support
of their children. Or if the catastrophe were unexpected and killed us
all outright, there would be no pain or suffering but many lives would
be prematurely cut off – a real harm, on any plausible view, to those
concerned.3
To isolate the central question, let us simplify things. Suppose it is
written in The Book of Fate that one day we will be wiped out in a nasty
catastrophe. Many millions of people will die in terrifying circumstances
involving great pain and distress. The only thing the Book of Fate is
silent about is when this is going to happen. It may be next year or it may
be many thousands of years from now. The question is – Should we care?
Does it matter how soon this happens?
One natural thought here is that the existence of human beings has
intrinsic value, impersonally regarded.4 And that therefore it is a good
thing that human beings should continue to exist for as long as possible.
This thought, though natural, is problematic. For one thing, it is not easy
to be very clear what the premise means – but as I want the conclusion of
this essay to lend some modest support to such scepticism, I’ll let this
pass for now and beg no questions. For another, it is by no means
obvious that the conclusion follows from it. It may be intrinsically good
that great works of music or literature should exist. But it is by no means
obvious that these works contribute more value by being longer.
To take a nearer analogy, consider some other species than our own
– the white rhino say. Suppose we are agreed that it is intrinsically good
that there are white rhinos. Does it follow that it is good if there continue
to be white rhinos for as long as possible? It is by no means clear that it
does. Imagine a bizarre possible world in which white rhinos are the only
living things – bizarre because impossible on both ecological and evolu-
tionary grounds but for the sake of argument let that pass. (In those
worlds where there is a God, God can do what he likes. In this world,
God miraculously brings white rhinos into being and miraculously stops
them from starving.) Let’s agree, again for the sake of argument, that
this is a good thing: this world is better for having white rhinos. Given
that, is there any reason to suppose this world better if there continue to
be white rhinos for longer – say for five billion rather than five million
years?
It is hard to see that it does. Consider after all a simpler question. Does
it matter, independently of how long white rhinos go on existing, how
large their population is? We can distinguish here the claims:
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM255
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
256 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY
A. It is better if there continue to be things of type F for as long as
possible.
B. It is better if there are as many things of type F as possible.
B is different from A given that there are both synchronic and diachronic
ways of being numerous. Making things better according to A in par-
ticular might be preferred if we suppose that, other things equal, the
diachronic ways are better. Alternatively we might suppose making things
better according to A is simply a means to doing so according to B – a
way to have more Fs is to have more and more generations of Fs stretch-
ing out into future time. But of course this is not the only way. However
many Fs there are one can always have more Fs without having to have
Fs for longer: one can simply have more Fs at a given time.
When we consider synchronically the size of the white rhino population
it is not clear that it matters how large that population is. If what matters
is the instantiation of the universal – white rhino or whatever – that is
already, as it were, taken care of. Of course, if there were fewer white
rhinos, it might be said that individuals of that species that might have
existed will fail to exist and perhaps those individuals have intrinsic value.5
But it is unclear that anything follows from this. No matter what happens,
we can always suppose there to be an infinity of possible individuals who
never get to exist. But it is hard to make much sense of the thought that
this a bad thing – either for those individuals themselves or otherwise.6 If
it is unclear how it would make things better to stretch out, synchronically,
in a single generation, the numbers of white rhinos, it is unclear why it
should make things better to stretch them out diachronically by having
more generations. Given that B is not very compelling, why suppose that
A is?7
The suggestion might be made8 that, if we allow that a world is made
better by the presence in it of some valued thing such as white rhinos, we
might motivate the thought that A has plausibility independently from B
by thinking of temporal parts of the world as, in effect, new worlds.
Maybe; but now the burden is surely on friends of this suggestion to say
a great deal more before it starts to look at all promising. For very
evidently temporal parts of worlds are not worlds. It might nonetheless
be claimed that temporal parts of worlds are in some relevant way world-
like for axiological purposes. But what is supposed to motivate this
thought? And, crucially, it stands in need not only of motivation but of
some motivation that would not generalize to our also so viewing spatial
parts of worlds. For that would, in the first place, restore A and B to an
equal footing and, in the second place, be deeply implausible. Many
people might view with regret the absence from a world of white rhinos
but it is a hugely doubtful basis for regret that there are no white rhinos
in northern Scotland.9 Indeed the plausibility of the temporal parts claim
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM256
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
ON BECOMING EXTINCT 257
is questionable in similar ways. We may think it a wonderful thing that
the world contains many examples of jazz music, but how much should
we regret its absence from, say, the world in the sixteenth century?
It does not follow from these considerations that it is not a bad thing
if, in the actual world, the white rhino becomes extinct sooner rather than
later. For one thing, we may attach value to natural biodiversity.10 Given
that there are living species in existence at a given time, perhaps it is
better if there are a rich diversity of species rather than only a few. This
diversity is diluted when the white rhino, say, disappears and that is why
the extinction of the white rhino would be a bad thing.
If we focus on natural biodiversity, we can make some sense of why the
ongoing extinction of countless species is to be regretted. Assuming this
explanation is convincing, it does have a couple of limitations. For one
thing, we cannot in this way make any sense of the thought that the
eventual extinction of every species is an event that is better postponed.
The value of natural biodiversity implies that, while there is life on earth,
it is good that there should be a significant natural diversity of such life.
It need not be read as implying that the inevitable disappearance of all
life on earth is something that is better happening later rather than sooner.
Moreover the appeal to natural biodiversity is quite unpromising when
we try to apply it to human beings. For the contribution to natural bio-
diversity of human beings has, in recent times, been overwhelmingly negat-
ive. Those who stress the value of natural biodiversity are alarmed in
particular at the sort of catastrophically rapid mass extinction over which
they fear we are presiding. As far as this good is concerned it would plau-
sibly be just wonderful if human beings disappeared as soon as possible.11
Another quite general reason for regretting the extinction of any spe-
cies might appeal to the more abstract – and more doubtful – value of
plenitude. Perhaps we want to say it is a bad thing when possibilities go
unrealized. Think in particular of the huge space of genetic possibilities,
Dennett’s “Library of Mendel”.12 Were we to disappear from the scene,
countless possibilities in this library would be cut off including perhaps
many that might contribute great value in the world.
I doubt if this thought is at all promising in the present context. In the
first place, at the most abstract level, it is unclear whether the principle is
remotely plausible. In the vast logical space of possible chess games there
are huge numbers that will never be played, a number of them no doubt
rather beautiful (if you like that sort of thing). Do we really think this
matters very much? It doesn’t amount to much of a reason why you and
I, right now, should play a game of chess. And it would certainly be a
reason altogether disconnected from the reasons that ordinarily actuate
real chess players.
Turning to the specific biological version of the claim, even if it is plaus-
ible, it is unclear how it would speak against our own extinction precisely
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM257
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
258 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY
because, as I just now observed, our own extinction would very likely do
more good than harm to natural biodiversity and consequently to the range
of genetic possibilities likely to turn up in the future course of evolution-
ary history. Even were we not so remarkably destructive a species, our
extinction coming not as part of a mass extinction but as an isolated event
would make a large difference to which genetic possibilities the future saw
realized but plausibly very little or none to how many were realized. Indeed
it is strictly false that any as yet unrealized possibilities in Mendel’s library
would be foreclosed by our extinction. There is no point in the logical
space of possible genotypes accessible some day to our descendants that
is not likewise accessible in principle to, say, the descendants of other
animals. Of course for very many such points it is astronomically improb-
able that the descendants of other animals will ever attain it but the same
can be said of most such points with respect to our own descendants.
3.
These general considerations of biodiversity, plenitude or raw intrinsic
value that might be brought to bear to urge regret at the extinction of any
biological species do not then get us very far in considering the fate of
our own. We might reasonably then turn to the things that are special
about our species, things that distinguish us from white rhinos, cacti or
plankton. There are plenty of candidates, to be sure: that we are rational,
that we have language, that we are self-conscious, that we are capable of
moral agency, that we are made in God’s image or simply that we are
human. With all but the last of these it is of course questionable whether
we are unique satisfiers of these descriptions and with all of them it is
questionable how much is supposed to follow morally if we are.
So it is hard to know where to start. Here it will help to recall again the
distinction between A and B above. We want to distinguish the question
Does it matter how long humanity lasts? – from the question Does it matter,
in absolute terms, how many human beings there are? Considered synchron-
ically, the overwhelmingly plausible answer to the latter question is: No.
Within the utilitarian tradition this answer is controversial, but it is plaus-
ible enough for it to be widely taken as a reductio of total utilitarianism
that it appears to imply otherwise.13 In any case, I will here assume a
negative answer as it is not my present aim to add to the considerable
literature on the issue.14 But if B is not compelling, why should A be?
Focusing on this helps us to see what not to focus on in terms of what is
special to human beings. If beings with reversible thumbs are intrinsically
valuable in ways that make it better the more of them there are, that would
support both A and B. And that is not the result we want. So we want to
look for something that makes sense of our regarding A and B differently.
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM258
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
ON BECOMING EXTINCT 259
There is one aspect in particular of human beings that looks rather
more promising here, an aspect in which human beings differ markedly
from other species. Not only do individual human lives have a certain
narrative structure but so too, given our unique endowment with lan-
guage, writing and culture does human history. And when we think of the
prospect of human extinction, perhaps we think of it as an evil in the
same way as we think of the premature death of an individual as an evil.
If we have read our Wells or Stapledon or Asimov we may be caught up
in some capitalized vision of The Future and think of extinction as tragic-
ally robbing us of that future much as the death of a child might tragically
rob her of her future. Certainly, if we have such a future, our descendants
will then look back on our own times as, in a sense, the childhood of our
race much as we, from our perspective, might so view the time of the
early hominids.
The thought is not novel. Jonathan Bennett has classed the career of
Homo Sapiens among those “great long adventures which it would be a
shame to have broken off short.”15 And Gregory Kavka has highlighted
the analogy between the narrative structure of our species’ history and
that of an individual life.16 But it is vital to appreciate how fragile the
analogy is in one crucial respect. If someone dies aged twenty-five, that is
tragic because it cheats them of the normal and natural span of a human
life. If someone dies aged ninety-five, though we mourn their passing,
their death is not tragic in the same way or for the same reason. But it is
implausible to suppose that human history – or that of any species – has
a natural narrative structure in the same way as a human life.
We might have taken it to have such a structure if we had some large
philosophical vision of human history as making sense in terms of some
readily discernible goal which it might be tragic not to attain. I take it
very few of us today are gripped by such a vision. If human beings go on
for countless millennia, today will seem to have been the childhood of
our species. If we disappear tomorrow today will seem (to some imagin-
ary observing aliens) to have been its old age. If we reject grand philo-
sophical pictures that endow human history with some essential pattern,
all that can be meant by metaphorical talk of our species’ childhood is
those times that are relatively early in its career whenever they may turn
out to be. The individual human tragedy of dying young has no obvious
analogue in the career of our species as a whole.17
Perhaps we still want to insist on the big narrative – perhaps we might
be attracted by a large conception of human historical purpose without
understanding this in terms of some final end point furnishing a goal we
should seek to attain; but rather in terms of some overarching ideal of
progress, some ladder we see ourselves ascending on which we should
aim to maximize the height we will attain. This would break any close
analogy with the good of individual human longevity but might allow us
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM259
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
260 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY
to make sense of the thought that our extinction is something better
postponed.
It is not clear however that there is any convincing way for this ideal of
progress to be filled out. Those that look most tempting are liable to
grow less so on close inspection. Thus some have been gripped by a view
of biological evolution – whether by natural or artificial selection – as
a meliorative progress whose advancement gives meaning and value to
our history, but there seem to be abundant grounds for scepticism about
both the moral and the scientific credibility of any such picture. Or, on a
cultural level, we might cite the advancement of knowledge and science
as giving our species a purpose that warrants belief in the impersonal
value of its maximally long continuance. Undoubtedly we often do invest
value in just this large and abstract project though plausibly the real
lifeblood of scientific motivation lies in more local manifestations of
curiosity, in more particular intellectual projects, in the desire to know
this or that rather than the bare desire to know – the desire (de dicto!) to
know lots of stuff. Nor can any such grand scientific project plausibly be
anything like the whole story – for science is only one of many human
projects and commitments, and one at whose cutting edge the vast major-
ity of those whose lives we value are not significantly engaged. And other
human projects and commitments tend to subsume still less readily in
any analogously conceived overarching master project.
It might still be insisted here that we want human beings to be all they
can be, fully to develop and explore their capacities. But let us note the
ambiguity in this thought: who is understood here by ‘human beings’? To
view the matter in microcosm, suppose I want my children to be all they
can be. How can I better promote this end? Well, I can do more to create
educational and other opportunities for them and encourage them to
take them. Or I can simply seek to have more and more children. We
naturally want to have children and when we have them, we naturally
want the children we have to excel. But we do not naturally want – and it
would be odd to say we should – the excellence of our children in any
way that might sensibly motivate me to keep on procreating until an
Olympic athlete turns up. Similarly with human beings it is one – very
natural – thing to want all the human beings there will in fact be to make
the most of themselves, another – far less natural – to want there to be
more and more human beings so that, collectively, we can the more
maximally exhaust the possibilities before us.18
4.
Recall that our question was not Is it a bad thing that we will one day
become extinct? but Given that we will become extinct, is it a bad thing if
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM260
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
ON BECOMING EXTINCT 261
this happens sooner rather than later? Given that this is what we are
asking it is not clear that considerations of how awful extinction will be
for those to whom it actually happens are any help at all. For this is going
to happen anyway. All we can say is that we do not want these bad things
to happen sooner rather than later. But, from an impersonal standpoint,
it makes no very obvious difference, given that they will happen some-
time, when they happen.
A natural rejoinder is that this consideration does not move us
much because we do not occupy so impersonal a standpoint.19 There
will be some generation, sometime, that will be overtaken by these
terrible events. I know this but I do not want it to be my generation; to
be the generation of those I most care for. Nor do I want it to be
the generation of my children – if I have any – or grandchildren or the
children and grandchildren of people who matter to me. When I con-
template the possibility that humans might soon die out, all kinds of
de re sentimental attachments may inform the alarm I might feel at this.
The thought of the streets I walk to work along emptied of human life
and the people who live there killed is one I naturally find peculiarly
distressing – or would if circumstances arose that made such a danger
feel imminent. The thought of a like fate overtaking the unimaginable
science fiction landscape that might be those same streets in the ninth
millennium might inspire in me a certain distant sadness. But it is a very
distant sadness at the prospect of a distant tragedy, very like the distant
sadness one might feel on reading about some cataclysm in the ancient
world.
Plausibly, I wish to propose, wanting there to be a next generation and
wanting it to thrive is a sentiment akin to and continuous with wanting
to have children and wanting them to thrive. The desire to have children
is a selfish sort of sentiment, to be sure, but in a peculiar and complicated
way. Partly it is a matter of wanting there to be a constituency for that
range of our moral and altruistic instincts that we bring to bear on
our immediate successors. If there is no such constituency, our lives are
impoverished in central and vital ways. The desire for – as the song has it
– somebody to love is that peculiarly sociable form of selfishness that is
fundamental to human moral community.20 Given that there will inevit-
ably be some generation for which there is no successor generation,
I nonetheless do not want it to be mine – ascending to something closer
to a moral point of view, I do not want it to be ours.
I suggested above that it did not matter, in absolute terms, how many
human beings there are. I can now explain the qualification. It may mat-
ter greatly to Bill and Mary that they have children. And if this matters,
it matters that the number of human beings there have been to date gets
larger than it presently is. For it must do if Bill and Mary are to have
the children they want. But while such concerns are important, no value
PAPQ83.3C04 7/31/02, 1:03 PM261
© 2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
262 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY
attaches to the absolute numbers involved. The value in Bill and Mary
having children is not a matter of its taking the species as a whole beyond,
say, that crucial 20 billion watershed. Likewise it may matter to every-
body – or almost everybody – in the present – or in any – generation that
there be a next generation.
Consider that old favourite of the literature on average utilitarianism –
the reasons Adam and Eve might have to have children.21 I would doubt
that they have reasons of a quite general and impersonal kind. I would
doubt too that they have reasons stemming from the narrative shape
of human history as a whole. But they do have the familiar reasons we all
– or most of us – have to have children. They may aim to enrich their
own lives by having something beyond their own happiness to shape and
give direction to their concerns, capacities and energies.22 It would surely
be a bizarre misunderstanding to call such reasons selfish in any sense
which contrasts them starkly with more ethical forms of motivation. None-
theless we are not here in the domain of narrowly moral reasons, where
these are understood as bound up with obligation.23
Let us note here too that, while the overall narrative structure of
human history has little work to do here, much greater relevance may
attach to all manner of more intermediate narratives.24 For Adam and
Eve may have all manner of projects and commitments that cannot be
contained in a single life and that call for the cooperation of successor
generations. Adam, Eve or both may be deeply concerned with the com-
pletion of the projects of turning that bit of space behind the house into
a garden, of getting the details right on that fancy new ploughing device
they were working on, of figuring out just how plants breed or of solving
Fermat’s last theorem. Such projects widen our interests beyond our own
lifetimes. It was good for Darwin that his ideas on evolution were vindic-
ated by modern genetics; good for Mallory that Everest was eventually
climbed and good for those who died fighting the Nazis that the Nazis
were finally defeated.25
Such intermediate narrative structures, like the structures of …
Philosophy of Death: DUE TOMORROW!
Answer the following question in a 4 FULL pages (NOT including cover page & citation page) TimesNewRoman, 12, double-spaced essay. Only use citation from the 2 pdf articles attached.
Given the readings about the 2 pdf files attached, Would human extinction be bad? Go in Depth and remember it’s a philosophy paper!
Have the thesis sentence underline in INTRO
Is it bad that the human race will someday become extinct? How does the badness of human extinction (if you think it would be bad) relate to the badness of the death of an individual person (if you think that would be bad)?
Your answers should reflect a familiarity with the material of the 2 PDF files attached, and all quotes must be properly cited for ONLY the pdf files attached
Use the checklist below:
A good paper is more than the sum of its parts, but the parts matter. Here’s a list of some things to check for before turning in your paper:
· There is an introduction.
· The introduction clearly states the thesis of your paper—that is, the introduction says what your ultimate answer to the paper’s question will be.
· The introduction clearly states what the outline of your paper will be.
· You thoroughly explain the relevant parts of the philosophers you’re talking about.
· The explanation of the philosophers is written such that someone who had not read them could understand it.
· There’s a clear distinction between the parts of your paper where you’re explaining what a philosopher said and where you’re interpreting or evaluating what they said.
· You clearly state your own answer to the question (or questions) of the paper.
· You give reasons for why your answer is correct, and why it’s better than the alternative. These reasons would make sense to any reasonable person who read them.
· There are appropriate quotes from the article used (about one per page is good).
· All quotes are properly cited with author and page in parentheses.
· There’s a Work Cited section at the end of your paper with an entry for each person your quote, including: Author, Title, Publisher / Journal name, Year.
· Each paragraph discusses only one idea.
· Transitions between paragraphs make sense.
· The final draft was spell-checked / grammar-checked.
Philosophy
of Death
:
DUE TOMORROW!
Answer the following question
in a
4 FULL pages (NOT including cover page & citation
page) TimesNewRoman, 12, double
-
spaced essay.
Only use citation from the
2
pdf articles attached.
Given the readings
about the 2 pdf file
s
attached,
Would human extinction
be bad?
Go in Depth and remembe
r
it’s a philosophy paper!
Have the thesis se
ntence underline in
INTRO
Is it bad that the human race will someday become extinct? How does the
badness of human extinction (if you think it would be bad) relate to the
badness of the death of an individual person (if you think that would be
bad)?
Your answers should reflect a familiarity with the material
of the 2 PDF files attached
,
and all quotes must be properly cited
for ONLY the pdf files attached
Use the checklist below:
A good paper is more than the sum of its parts, but the parts matter.
Here’s a list of
some things to check for before turning in your paper:
¨
There is an introduction.
¨
The introduction clearly states the thesis of your paper
—
that is, the introduction
says what your ultimate answer to the paper’s question will be.
¨
The int
roduction clearly states what the outline of your paper will be.
¨
You thoroughly explain the relevant parts of the philosophers you’re talking
about.
¨
The explanation of the philosophers is written such that someone who had not
read them could understand i
t.
¨
There’s a clear distinction between the parts of your paper where you’re
explaining what a philosopher said and where you’re interpreting or evaluating
what they said.
¨
You clearly state your own answer to the question (or questions) of the
paper.
Philosophy of Death: DUE TOMORROW!
Answer the following question in a 4 FULL pages (NOT including cover page & citation
page) TimesNewRoman, 12, double-spaced essay. Only use citation from the 2
pdf articles attached.
Given the readings about the 2 pdf files attached, Would human extinction
be bad? Go in Depth and remember it’s a philosophy paper!
Have the thesis sentence underline in INTRO
Is it bad that the human race will someday become extinct? How does the
badness of human extinction (if you think it would be bad) relate to the
badness of the death of an individual person (if you think that would be
bad)?
Your answers should reflect a familiarity with the material of the 2 PDF files attached,
and all quotes must be properly cited for ONLY the pdf files attached
Use the checklist below:
A good paper is more than the sum of its parts, but the parts matter. Here’s a list of
some things to check for before turning in your paper:
There is an introduction.
The introduction clearly states the thesis of your paper—that is, the introduction
says what your ultimate answer to the paper’s question will be.
The introduction clearly states what the outline of your paper will be.
You thoroughly explain the relevant parts of the philosophers you’re talking
about.
The explanation of the philosophers is written such that someone who had not
read them could understand it.
There’s a clear distinction between the parts of your paper where you’re
explaining what a philosopher said and where you’re interpreting or evaluating
what they said.
You clearly state your own answer to the question (or questions) of the paper.
CATEGORIES
Economics
Nursing
Applied Sciences
Psychology
Science
Management
Computer Science
Human Resource Management
Accounting
Information Systems
English
Anatomy
Operations Management
Sociology
Literature
Education
Business & Finance
Marketing
Engineering
Statistics
Biology
Political Science
Reading
History
Financial markets
Philosophy
Mathematics
Law
Criminal
Architecture and Design
Government
Social Science
World history
Chemistry
Humanities
Business Finance
Writing
Programming
Telecommunications Engineering
Geography
Physics
Spanish
ach
e. Embedded Entrepreneurship
f. Three Social Entrepreneurship Models
g. Social-Founder Identity
h. Micros-enterprise Development
Outcomes
Subset 2. Indigenous Entrepreneurship Approaches (Outside of Canada)
a. Indigenous Australian Entrepreneurs Exami
Calculus
(people influence of
others) processes that you perceived occurs in this specific Institution Select one of the forms of stratification highlighted (focus on inter the intersectionalities
of these three) to reflect and analyze the potential ways these (
American history
Pharmacology
Ancient history
. Also
Numerical analysis
Environmental science
Electrical Engineering
Precalculus
Physiology
Civil Engineering
Electronic Engineering
ness Horizons
Algebra
Geology
Physical chemistry
nt
When considering both O
lassrooms
Civil
Probability
ions
Identify a specific consumer product that you or your family have used for quite some time. This might be a branded smartphone (if you have used several versions over the years)
or the court to consider in its deliberations. Locard’s exchange principle argues that during the commission of a crime
Chemical Engineering
Ecology
aragraphs (meaning 25 sentences or more). Your assignment may be more than 5 paragraphs but not less.
INSTRUCTIONS:
To access the FNU Online Library for journals and articles you can go the FNU library link here:
https://www.fnu.edu/library/
In order to
n that draws upon the theoretical reading to explain and contextualize the design choices. Be sure to directly quote or paraphrase the reading
ce to the vaccine. Your campaign must educate and inform the audience on the benefits but also create for safe and open dialogue. A key metric of your campaign will be the direct increase in numbers.
Key outcomes: The approach that you take must be clear
Mechanical Engineering
Organic chemistry
Geometry
nment
Topic
You will need to pick one topic for your project (5 pts)
Literature search
You will need to perform a literature search for your topic
Geophysics
you been involved with a company doing a redesign of business processes
Communication on Customer Relations. Discuss how two-way communication on social media channels impacts businesses both positively and negatively. Provide any personal examples from your experience
od pressure and hypertension via a community-wide intervention that targets the problem across the lifespan (i.e. includes all ages).
Develop a community-wide intervention to reduce elevated blood pressure and hypertension in the State of Alabama that in
in body of the report
Conclusions
References (8 References Minimum)
*** Words count = 2000 words.
*** In-Text Citations and References using Harvard style.
*** In Task section I’ve chose (Economic issues in overseas contracting)"
Electromagnetism
w or quality improvement; it was just all part of good nursing care. The goal for quality improvement is to monitor patient outcomes using statistics for comparison to standards of care for different diseases
e a 1 to 2 slide Microsoft PowerPoint presentation on the different models of case management. Include speaker notes... .....Describe three different models of case management.
visual representations of information. They can include numbers
SSAY
ame workbook for all 3 milestones. You do not need to download a new copy for Milestones 2 or 3. When you submit Milestone 3
pages):
Provide a description of an existing intervention in Canada
making the appropriate buying decisions in an ethical and professional manner.
Topic: Purchasing and Technology
You read about blockchain ledger technology. Now do some additional research out on the Internet and share your URL with the rest of the class
be aware of which features their competitors are opting to include so the product development teams can design similar or enhanced features to attract more of the market. The more unique
low (The Top Health Industry Trends to Watch in 2015) to assist you with this discussion.
https://youtu.be/fRym_jyuBc0
Next year the $2.8 trillion U.S. healthcare industry will finally begin to look and feel more like the rest of the business wo
evidence-based primary care curriculum. Throughout your nurse practitioner program
Vignette
Understanding Gender Fluidity
Providing Inclusive Quality Care
Affirming Clinical Encounters
Conclusion
References
Nurse Practitioner Knowledge
Mechanics
and word limit is unit as a guide only.
The assessment may be re-attempted on two further occasions (maximum three attempts in total). All assessments must be resubmitted 3 days within receiving your unsatisfactory grade. You must clearly indicate “Re-su
Trigonometry
Article writing
Other
5. June 29
After the components sending to the manufacturing house
1. In 1972 the Furman v. Georgia case resulted in a decision that would put action into motion. Furman was originally sentenced to death because of a murder he committed in Georgia but the court debated whether or not this was a violation of his 8th amend
One of the first conflicts that would need to be investigated would be whether the human service professional followed the responsibility to client ethical standard. While developing a relationship with client it is important to clarify that if danger or
Ethical behavior is a critical topic in the workplace because the impact of it can make or break a business
No matter which type of health care organization
With a direct sale
During the pandemic
Computers are being used to monitor the spread of outbreaks in different areas of the world and with this record
3. Furman v. Georgia is a U.S Supreme Court case that resolves around the Eighth Amendments ban on cruel and unsual punishment in death penalty cases. The Furman v. Georgia case was based on Furman being convicted of murder in Georgia. Furman was caught i
One major ethical conflict that may arise in my investigation is the Responsibility to Client in both Standard 3 and Standard 4 of the Ethical Standards for Human Service Professionals (2015). Making sure we do not disclose information without consent ev
4. Identify two examples of real world problems that you have observed in your personal
Summary & Evaluation: Reference & 188. Academic Search Ultimate
Ethics
We can mention at least one example of how the violation of ethical standards can be prevented. Many organizations promote ethical self-regulation by creating moral codes to help direct their business activities
*DDB is used for the first three years
For example
The inbound logistics for William Instrument refer to purchase components from various electronic firms. During the purchase process William need to consider the quality and price of the components. In this case
4. A U.S. Supreme Court case known as Furman v. Georgia (1972) is a landmark case that involved Eighth Amendment’s ban of unusual and cruel punishment in death penalty cases (Furman v. Georgia (1972)
With covid coming into place
In my opinion
with
Not necessarily all home buyers are the same! When you choose to work with we buy ugly houses Baltimore & nationwide USA
The ability to view ourselves from an unbiased perspective allows us to critically assess our personal strengths and weaknesses. This is an important step in the process of finding the right resources for our personal learning style. Ego and pride can be
· By Day 1 of this week
While you must form your answers to the questions below from our assigned reading material
CliftonLarsonAllen LLP (2013)
5 The family dynamic is awkward at first since the most outgoing and straight forward person in the family in Linda
Urien
The most important benefit of my statistical analysis would be the accuracy with which I interpret the data. The greatest obstacle
From a similar but larger point of view
4 In order to get the entire family to come back for another session I would suggest coming in on a day the restaurant is not open
When seeking to identify a patient’s health condition
After viewing the you tube videos on prayer
Your paper must be at least two pages in length (not counting the title and reference pages)
The word assimilate is negative to me. I believe everyone should learn about a country that they are going to live in. It doesnt mean that they have to believe that everything in America is better than where they came from. It means that they care enough
Data collection
Single Subject Chris is a social worker in a geriatric case management program located in a midsize Northeastern town. She has an MSW and is part of a team of case managers that likes to continuously improve on its practice. The team is currently using an
I would start off with Linda on repeating her options for the child and going over what she is feeling with each option. I would want to find out what she is afraid of. I would avoid asking her any “why” questions because I want her to be in the here an
Summarize the advantages and disadvantages of using an Internet site as means of collecting data for psychological research (Comp 2.1) 25.0\% Summarization of the advantages and disadvantages of using an Internet site as means of collecting data for psych
Identify the type of research used in a chosen study
Compose a 1
Optics
effect relationship becomes more difficult—as the researcher cannot enact total control of another person even in an experimental environment. Social workers serve clients in highly complex real-world environments. Clients often implement recommended inte
I think knowing more about you will allow you to be able to choose the right resources
Be 4 pages in length
soft MB-920 dumps review and documentation and high-quality listing pdf MB-920 braindumps also recommended and approved by Microsoft experts. The practical test
g
One thing you will need to do in college is learn how to find and use references. References support your ideas. College-level work must be supported by research. You are expected to do that for this paper. You will research
Elaborate on any potential confounds or ethical concerns while participating in the psychological study 20.0\% Elaboration on any potential confounds or ethical concerns while participating in the psychological study is missing. Elaboration on any potenti
3 The first thing I would do in the family’s first session is develop a genogram of the family to get an idea of all the individuals who play a major role in Linda’s life. After establishing where each member is in relation to the family
A Health in All Policies approach
Note: The requirements outlined below correspond to the grading criteria in the scoring guide. At a minimum
Chen
Read Connecting Communities and Complexity: A Case Study in Creating the Conditions for Transformational Change
Read Reflections on Cultural Humility
Read A Basic Guide to ABCD Community Organizing
Use the bolded black section and sub-section titles below to organize your paper. For each section
Losinski forwarded the article on a priority basis to Mary Scott
Losinksi wanted details on use of the ED at CGH. He asked the administrative resident